• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Abstract. We are concerned with C

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Abstract. We are concerned with C"

Copied!
28
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

148 (1995)

Classification of function spaces with the pointwise topology determined

by a countable dense set

by

Tadeusz D o b r o w o l s k i (Norman, Okla.) and Witold M a r c i s z e w s k i (Warszawa)

Abstract. We are concerned with C

A

(X), the space of continuous real valued func- tions on X considered with the topology of pointwise convergence on A, where A is a countable dense subset of X. We focus on the Borel and the topological classifications of the spaces C

A

(X). For example, we prove that for countable nondiscrete X, C

A

(X) is homeomorphic to σ

ω

, the countable product of σ = {(x

i

) ∈ R

ω

| x

i

= 0 a.e.}, provided C

A

(X) ∈ F

σδ

.

1. Introduction. All spaces under consideration are completely regu- lar. For a space X, C

p

(X) denotes the space of all continuous real valued functions on X with the pointwise convergence topology. If A is a dense subset of X, then by C

A

(X) we denote the space of continuous real valued functions on X with the topology of pointwise convergence on A. Hence, we have C

A

(X) = {f |A | f is continuous on X} ⊆ R

A

and C

X

(X) = C

p

(X).

Throughout this paper we will assume that A is countable; consequently, C

A

(X) is a dense linear subspace of R

A

, a countable product of lines.

Recently, a lot of work has been done on the topological classification of Borel and projective function spaces C

p

(X) for countable spaces X (for references see [DMM] and [CDM]). It has been shown that C

p

(X), while Borel, is always of an exact multiplicative class [CDM] and it is conjectured that the topological and the Borel classifications coincide [DMM]. For the countable spaces X the spaces C

A

(X) seem to be a natural generalization

1991 Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary 46E10, 57N20, 54C35.

Key words and phrases: function space, topology determined by a countable set, bor- elian filters.

Research of the second author partially supported by KBN grant 2 1113 91 01.

The results of this paper were presented by the second author in January 1993 at the 21st Winter School on Abstract Analysis, Podˇebrady, Czech Republic.

[35]

(2)

of the spaces C

p

(X). This paper is to initiate an investigation on the Borel complexity and the topological classification of the spaces C

A

(X). The Borel structure of the spaces C

A

(X) seems to be much more complicated than in the case of C

p

(X). However, we are able to indicate some similarities between the topological classifications of the spaces C

A

(X) and C

p

(X).

The spaces C

A

(X) also allow us to use some methods of descriptive set theory and infinite-dimensional topology (applicable for separable metriz- able spaces) for the investigation of the function spaces on uncountable separable spaces. In this context the spaces C

A

(X) have appeared in the literature in several natural situations. Before we describe some of them we have to recall a few notions.

A map f : M → N between separable metrizable spaces is of the first Baire class if f

−1

(U ) is an F

σ

-subset of M for every open U ⊂ N (if N is additionally a linear space then this means that f is the pointwise limit of a sequence of continuous maps M → N ). Let P be the space of irrationals.

It turns out that compact spaces that can be embedded in B

1

(P ), the space of real valued first Baire class functions on P with the topology of pointwise convergence, are of great importance in topology and Banach space theory (see [BFT] and [Ne, Section 1]); they are called Rosenthal compacta. The following result of Godefroy [Go, Theorem 4] shows how C

A

(X) spaces are involved in dealing with Rosenthal compacta.

1.1. A separable compact space K is a Rosenthal compactum if and only if for every countable dense subset A of K the space C

A

(K) is analytic (i.e., a continuous image of P ).

The problem of Borel classification of the spaces C

A

(K) for separable Rosenthal compact spaces K has been disscussed in [Ma1].

Another important fact involving C

A

(X) spaces is the following factor- ization result [Ma1, Lemma 3.4]:

1.2. Let X and Y be separable spaces and ϕ : C

p

(X) → C

p

(Y ) be a homeomorphism. For any countable sets C ⊆ X and D ⊆ Y there exist countable dense sets A ⊆ X and B ⊆ Y such that C ⊆ A, D ⊆ B and the map π

B

ϕπ

A−1

: C

A

(X) → C

B

(Y ) is a homeomorphism (π

A

: C

p

(X) → C

A

(X) and π

B

: C

p

(Y ) → C

B

(X) are the standard projections).

This result shows that the problem of the topological classification of the function spaces C

p

(X) for separable spaces X is related to the problem of the classification of the spaces C

A

(X).

Let us observe that the topology of C

A

(X) is precisely the weak topology

on C

p

(X) induced by the family of evaluation functionals at a, a ∈ A; this

family is countable, consists of continuous linear functionals, and separates

points of C

p

(X). Any continuous linear functional on C

p

(X) is a linear com-

(3)

bination of finitely many evaluation functionals (at x ∈ X). The following example shows that the weak topology on C

p

(X) induced by a countable family of continuous linear functionals which separate points of C

p

(X) is not necessarily that of C

A

(X) for some countable dense A ⊆ X.

1.3. Example. Let {q

n

}

n=1

be an enumeration of the rationals in the line R. The sequence {ϕ

n

}

n=1

of continuous linear functionals on C

p

(R) given by ϕ

n

(f ) = f (q

n

) + f (q

n

+ π/n), f ∈ C

p

(R), n = 1, 2, . . . , separates points of C

p

(R). However, every evaluation functional on C

p

(R) is discon- tinuous in the weak topology induced by {ϕ

n

}

n=1

on C

p

(R).

Recall that if M is a separable metrizable space and α is a countable ordi- nal then A

α

(M ) (resp., M

α

(M )) denotes the family of subsets of M that are Borel of additive (resp., multiplicative) class α. By A

α

(resp., M

α

) we de- note the class of spaces that are absolute Borel of additive (resp., multiplica- tive) class α. If A ∈ A

α

\M

α

(resp., M

α

\A

α

or A

α

∩M

α

\ S

β<α

(A

β

∪M

β

)), then we say that A is of the exact additive (resp., multiplicative or ambi- guous) class α. By P

n

, n ≥ 0, we denote the nth projective class. A map f : M → N between separable metrizable spaces is Borel of class α if f

−1

(U ) ∈ A

α

(M ) for every open U ⊂ N (this means that f is Borel of class α = 1 precisely when f is of the first Baire class). The above terminology is that of [Kur].

In Section 2 we address some questions concerning the Borel (projective) structure of spaces C

A

(X). For instance, fixing X, we wonder how the Borel (projective) class of C

A

(X) will change when varying A. The following in- teresting question arises. What is the relationship between the exact Borel (projective) classes of C

p

(X), C

A

(X) and C

p

(A) for countable X? For each countable ordinal α, we provide an example of a countable space X

α

and a dense subset A

α

so that C

p

(X

α

) ∈ M

2

and C

Aα

(X

α

) 6∈ M

α

(see 2.6).

In Section 3 we deal with spaces X with exactly one nonisolated point.

Such spaces can be identified with N

F

= N ∪ {∞} topologized by isolating the points of N = {1, 2, . . .} and using the family {A ∪ {∞} | A ∈ F } as a neighborhood base at ∞, where F is a filter on N. In our considerations, if F is a filter on a countable set T , then we usually identify T and N and most often we let T = ω = {0, 1, . . .}. We will always assume that F contains the Fr´echet filter F

0

consisting of all cofinite sets in ω. We will write

c

F

= {f ∈ R

ω

| ∀(ε > 0) (f

−1

((−ε, ε)) ∈ F )}

and

C

F

= {f ∈ R

ω

| ∃(x ∈ R)∀(ε > 0) (f

−1

((x − ε, x + ε)) ∈ F )}.

It is known [Ma2, Lemma 2.1] that c

F

is (linearly) homeomorphic to C

p

(N

F

).

The space C

F

can be identified with C

ω

(N

F

). Moreover, we have

C

F

= {f ∈ R

ω

| ∀(ε > 0)∃(A ∈ F )∀(a

1

, a

2

∈ A) (|f (a

1

) − f (a

2

)| < ε)}.

(4)

In these definitions the space ω can be replaced by any countable infinite set T . A filter F on T will be treated as a subset of 2

T

, a copy of the Cantor set. We address the following question. What is the relation between the Borel (projective) exact class of F and that of C

F

? Our answer is contained in 3.4 and is less satisfactory compared to the case of c

F

(see [DMM]).

Section 5 is devoted to the topological identification of F

σδ

-spaces C

A

(X).

The main result states that for countable nondiscrete X and dense A ⊆ X, the space C

A

(X) is homeomorphic to σ

ω

provided C

A

(X) ∈ F

σδ

; here σ = {(x

n

) ∈ R

ω

| x

n

= 0 a.e.}. (This fact for A = X is the main result of [DMM].) The same result holds for (not necessarily countable) Fr´echet spaces X. Let us recall that X is a Fr´echet space if given a subset Y ⊂ X and a point x ∈ Y there exists a sequence of elements of Y that converges to x. The main tool to obtain these identification results is the method of absorbing sets (belonging to infinite-dimensional topology, see [BM]).

An application of this technique to function spaces was initiated by van Mill in [vM]. We do not explicitly refer to this method; instead, we use some factorization facts and rely on results of [CDM]. However, we were not able to avoid another notion of infinite-dimensional topology: so-called Z

σ

-spaces. We devote Section 4 to Z

σ

-spaces C

A

(X). Many of our results concern also spaces C

A

(X), subsets of C

A

(X) consisting of all bounded functions.

In Section 6 we settle the case of metrizable X. It turns out that for a metrizable X, C

A

(X) is analytic only if X is σ-compact (and then, it is homeomorphic to σ

ω

).

In the last section we provide examples of spaces C

F

with arbitrarily high Borel complexity. This is achieved by employing filters F previously used in [CDM]. Here, as in [CDM], not only do we show that for every α ≥ 2 there exists a filter F such that C

F

∈ M

α

\ A

a

, but actually it follows that C

F

is an absorbing set for the class of M

α

. Hence, C

F

is homeomorphic to the standard, M

α

-absorbing model Ω

α

(see [BM]).

2. C

A

(X) versus C

B

(X). How much can they differ? For a space X and countable dense subsets A and B of X, we will be interested in how much the Borel (projective) classes of C

A

(X) and C

B

(X) can differ. The following estimate was established in [Ma1, Theorem 2.2].

2.1. Proposition. Let X be a Fr´echet space and let A, B ⊆ X be count- able dense sets. For every countable ordinal α and every n ∈ ω, we have:

(a) if C

A

(X) ∈ M

α

, then C

B

(X) ∈ M

1+α

,

(b) if C

A

(X) ∈ A

α

, then C

B

(X) ∈ A

1+α

,

(c) if C

A

(X) ∈ P

n

, then C

B

(X) ∈ P

n

.

(5)

In particular , for infinite ordinals α and n ∈ ω, the exact Borel (projective) classes of C

A

(X) and C

B

(X) coincide.

The following example shows that for non-Fr´echet spaces X the gap between Borel classes can be as big as we wish (for a space Z, βZ denotes the ˇ Cech–Stone compactification of Z).

2.2. Example. We have

(a) C

ω

(βω) ∈ A

1

\M

1

(actually, C

ω

(βω) can be identified with the space Σ = {(x

n

) ∈ R

ω

| (x

n

) is bounded}),

(b) if p is an ultrafilter on ω (i.e., p ∈ βω \ω), then C

ω∪{p}

(βω) 6∈ P

1

∪P

2

(actually, C

ω∪{p}

(βω) contains a closed copy of the ultrafilter p).

The statement of 2.2(b) can be reversed in the following way.

2.3. Proposition. Let X be a compact space. Assume there are count- able dense sets A, B ⊆ X such that C

A

(X) is analytic and C

B

(X) is non- analytic. Then X contains a copy of βω.

P r o o f. Write S = C

A

(X) and consider i : X → R

S

defined by i(x)(f ) = arctan(f (x)), f ∈ S, x ∈ X.

It follows that i is an embedding and i(K) is norm-bounded (here, we con- sider the sup norm on the space of bounded functions on S). Moreover, for a ∈ A, i(a) is continuous on S. Using the Godefroy characterization of Rosenthal compacta and our assumption, we get i(K) * B

1

(S). Now, our result is a consequence of the following statement from [P, p. 34] (see also [BFT]): “For an arbitrary norm-bounded sequence {f

j

| j ∈ ω} of continu- ous functions on P (or, more generally, on an analytic space X) one and only one possibility occurs: either all pointwise accumulation points of {f

j

} are of first Baire class, or there exists a subsequence {f

j

| j ∈ ω} which behaves on some Cantor set T in P like the sequence of projections p

j

: ω

ω

→ {0, 1}

(in particular, in the second case, all accumulation points of {f

j

| j ∈ ω} are non-Borel and the pointwise closure of the set {f

j

| j ∈ ω} is homeomorphic to the ˇ Cech–Stone compactification of the natural numbers”.

To get our assertion, enumerate A = {a

j

| j ∈ ω} and apply the above statement to the sequence {i(a

j

) | j ∈ ω}.

The following result is a direct consequence of 2.3 and 1.1.

2.4. Corollary. Let X be a compact space and let A be a countable dense subset of X. If C

A

(X) is analytic then either X is a Rosenthal com- pactum or else X contains a copy of βω.

It has been shown [CDM, Theorem 5.1] that for every countable space

X, the space C

p

(X), when Borel, is of an exact multiplicative class. In

connection with this and 2.2(a) we ask:

(6)

2.5. Question. Is there an example of a (countable) space X such that C

A

(X) ∈ A

α

\ M

α

, α > 1, for some countable dense set A ⊆ X?

Next we show that the gap between Borel classes of C

p

(X) = C

X

(X) and C

A

(X) can be large even for countable X.

2.6. Proposition. For every countable ordinal α, there exists a count- able space X

α

and a dense set A ⊆ X

α

such that C

p

(X

α

) ∈ M

2

and C

A

(X

α

) 6∈ M

α

.

P r o o f. We will use induction on α. Set X

0

= A = ω + 1. It is obvious that C

p

(X

0

) ∈ M

2

; by [DGM, Corollary 1.2], C

p

(X

0

) is homeomorphic to σ

ω

and hence it belongs to M

2

\ A

2

. Let us distinguish x

0

= ω ∈ X

0

and B

0

= ω; note that B

0

is the set of all isolated points of X

0

and A = B

0

∪{x

0

}.

Suppose the spaces X

β

have been constructed (for all β < α), sets B

β

of all isolated points of X

β

and points x

β

∈ X

β

\ B

β

have been determined so that A

β

= B

β

∪ {x

β

} is a countable dense subset of X

β

so that C

Aβ

(X

β

) 6∈

M

α

and C

p

(X

β

) ∈ M

2

. For every n ∈ ω, let α

n

= β provided α = β +1. If α is a limit ordinal, fix a sequence of ordinals {α

n

}

n∈ω

with α

n

< α, n ∈ ω, and sup

n

α

n

= α. Form a direct sum Y

α

= ( S

n∈ω

{n} × X

αn

) ⊕ (ω + 1). Consider an equivalence relation R on Y

α

which identifies (n, x

αn

) with n ∈ ω + 1.

We set X

α

= Y

α

/R to be the quotient space. Write q : Y

α

→ X

α

for the quotient map. We let

B

α

= {x ∈ X

α

| x is isolated in X

α

}

and x

α

= q(ω), where ω ∈ ω + 1. By the construction B

α

= S

n∈ω

q({n} × B

αn

). Finally, we let A

α

= B

α

∪ {x

α

} and observe that A

α

is countable and dense in X

α

. (Note that X

1

and A

1

are the Arens spaces described in Examples 1.6.19 and 1.6.20 of [En], respectively).

Observe that f is continuous on X

α

if and only if f |q({n} × X

αn

) and f |q(ω + 1), n ∈ ω, are continuous. It then inductively follows that C

p

(X

a

) ∈ M

2

. We now show that C

Aα

(X

α

) 6∈ M

α

. Consider the following subspaces E

α

and F

α

of C

Bα

(X

α

):

E

α

= {f ∈ C

Bα

(X

α

) ∩ {0, 1}

Bα

| f (x

α

) = 0}, F

α

= {f ∈ C

Bα

(X

α

) ∩ {0, 1}

Bα

| f (x

α

) = 1}.

Claim. Write G

α

= E

α

∪ F

α

. The pairs (G

α

, E

α

) and (G

α

, F

α

) are Wadge (2

ω

, A

α

∪ M

α

(2

ω

))-complete (i.e., for every C ∈ A

α

∪ M

α

(2

ω

) there exists a map ϕ : 2

ω

→ G

α

so that ϕ

−1

(E

α

) = C or ϕ

−1

(F

α

) = C, respec- tively).

We will provide an inductive proof. If α = 0, then E

0

and F

0

are copies of

the rationals and both E

0

and F

0

are dense in G

0

. Let C ∈ M

0

(2

ω

) (i.e., C

is a closed subset of 2

ω

). Pick a sequence {x

n

}

n=1

⊂ E

0

such that lim x

n

=

x

0

∈ F

0

. Find a map ϕ : 2

ω

→ {x

n

| n ∈ ω} such that ϕ

−1

({x

0

}) = C. If

(7)

C ∈ A

0

(2

ω

) (i.e., C is open in 2

ω

), apply the same argument interchanging the roles of E

0

and F

0

. Let C ∈ A

α

and pick C

n

∈ M

αn

, C

n

⊆ C

n+1

, n ∈ ω, so that C = S

n∈ω

C

n

. We have E

α

= FP(G

αn

, E

αn

) and F

α

= FP(G

αn

, F

αn

), where for a sequence {(X

n

, A

n

)}

n∈ω

of pairs of spaces

FP(X

n

, A

n

) = n

(x

n

) ∈ Y

n∈ω

X

n

x

n

∈ A

n

a.e.

o

(notation of [CDM, Section 8]). Using the inductive assumption, we can find ϕ

n

: 2

ω

→ G

αn

⊂ R

Bαn

such that ϕ

−1n

(E

αn

) = C

n

. Take ϕ = ∆ϕ

n

: 2

ω

→ R∪

Bαn

given by ϕ(p) = (ϕ

n

(p)) and observe that ϕ( S

n∈ω

C

n

) ⊂ FP(G

αn

, E

αn

) and ϕ(2

ω

\ S

n∈ω

C

n

) ⊂ Q

n∈ω

F

αn

⊂ F

α

(cf. [CDM, Proof of 8.1]). This settles the case where C ∈ A

α

. By symmetry the same argu- ment works for C ∈ M

α

.

An easy application of the Claim yields E

α

6∈ M

α

∪ A

α

. Since E

α

can be identified with the set

{f ∈ C

Aα

(X

α

) ∩ {0, 1}

Aα

| f (x

α

) = 0}, a closed subset of C

Aα

(X

α

), our assertion follows.

2.7. R e m a r k. Let us note that even for a compact X the Borel class of C

A

(X) can be as high as we wish. Such spaces X can be taken as Rosenthal compacta and were provided in [Ma1]. Let us indicate another way of finding such X. By [LvMP, Theorem 4.1], there exists a countable regular space A with exactly one nonisolated point such that the Borel class of C

p

(A) (and hence, of C

p

(A)) is as high as we wish. Let X = βA and observe that C

A

(X) = C

p

(A).

2.8. R e m a r k. Consider X = N

F

for a filter F on ω. Applying 3.3, we see that C

ω

(N

F

) = C

F

contains a closed copy of F ; and hence can have as complicated Borel structure as we wish. At the same time C

p

(ω) = R

ω

∈ M

1

.

The statements 2.6 and 2.8 show that, within the Borel hierarchy, the Borel class of C

A

(X) cannot be estimated by either the class of C

p

(X) or C

p

(A).

2.9. Question. Let X be a countable space and let A be a dense subset of X. Is the Borel (projective) class of C

p

(X) (resp., C

p

(A)) determined by that of C

A

(X)? Is C

p

(X) Borel (analytic) if C

A

(X) is? Can the exact Borel (projective) class of C

p

(X) be greater than that of C

A

(X)?

2.10. R e m a r k. Let π

A

: C

p

(X) → C

A

(X) be the projection map. Since

C

A

(X) = π

A

(C

p

(X)) and π

A

is injective, C

A

(X) is Borel provided C

p

(X)

is (see [Kur]). We claim that also C

p

(A) is analytic provided C

A

(X) is. The

latter can be shown as follows. If C

A

(X) is analytic, then for every accumu-

lation point a ∈ A the filter F

a

= {Y ∩A | Y ∈ 2

X\{a}

and a ∈ Int(Y ∪{a})}

(8)

is an analytic filter on A \ {a} (cf. the proof of [DMM, Corollary 3.6]). If now by A

Fa

we denote the space A topologized by isolating the points of A \ {a} and by using the family {A ∪ {a} | A ∈ F

a

} as neighborhood base at a, we have C

p

(A) = T

{C

p

(A

Fa

) | a is an accumulation point of A}.

Since each C

p

(A

Fa

) is analytic, so is C

p

(A) (this argument was taken from [DMM, Lemma 4.3]).

Let us notice that the last two questions of 2.9 have negative answers for bounded function spaces.

2.11. Example. For any ultrafilter p ∈ βω \ ω we have, C

ω

(ω ∪ {p}) = Σ ∈ A

1

\ M

1

and C

p

(ω ∪ {p}) 6∈ P

1

∪ P

2

.

Observe that, for every p from Example 2.11, we also have C

ω

(ω ∪{p}) 6∈

P

1

∪ P

2

. Hence, we see that the gap between Borel classes of C

A

(X) and C

A

(X) can be as big as we wish.

3. Borel type of spaces C

F

. For the Fr´echet filter F

0

on ω we use the classical functional analysis symbols c

0

and c to denote the spaces c

F0

and C

F0

. The spaces c

0

and c considered as Banach spaces (with the sup norm) are linearly isomorphic. The following fact shows a dramatic difference if one considers c

0

and c as subspaces of R

ω

.

3.1. Proposition. The spaces c

0

, c ⊂ R

ω

are not linearly isomorphic.

P r o o f. Assume T : c

0

→ c establishes a linear topological isomorphism of c

0

onto c. Let k · k be the sup-norm on c (and c

0

). First we note that the graph of T ,

Γ = {(x, T x) | x ∈ c

0

} ⊂ c

0

× c,

is closed in the norm topology. This follows from the obvious fact that Γ is closed with respect to the coordinatewise topology on c

0

×c and the fact that the latter topology is weaker than the norm topology on c

0

×c. Consequently, by the Closed Graph Theorem, T establishes a linear isomorphism of (c

0

, k·k) onto (c, k · k).

Consider the continuous linear functional ` : (c, k · k) → R given by

`((x

n

)) = lim x

n

. It follows that `◦T : (c

0

, k·k) → R is continuous and `◦T 6≡

0. This obviously implies that ` ◦ T is continuous with respect to the weak

topology ω on c

0

. Consequently, for every convex closed neighborhood U of

0 ∈ (c

0

, k·k), ker(`◦T )∩U is closed in the ω-topology, and ker(`◦T )∩U 6= U .

Let B = {y ∈ c | kyk ≤ 1} be the unit ball in c. We will show that for

U = T

−1

(B), ker(` ◦ T ) ∩ U is dense in U in the ω-topology, contradicting

the above fact. To this end, first notice that given y ∈ B, there exists a

sequence {y

n

}

n∈ω

⊂ B ∩ c

0

so that {y

n

}

n∈ω

converges to y in R

ω

. We see

that {T

−1

y

n

}

n∈ω

converges to T

−1

y in R

ω

and T

−1

y

n

∈ ker(` ◦ T ). Since

(9)

the ω-topology coincides with the R

ω

-topology on bounded sets, it follows that {T

−1

y

n

} converges to T

−1

y in the ω-topology.

Before we enter a discussion on Borel types of C

F

, let us formulate the following general fact which will be employed later on; its proof can be obtained easily by using the argument of the proof of [Ma2, Lemma 2.1].

3.2. Lemma. Let F be a filter on ω which is not the Fr´echet filter. Then C

F

is homeomorphic to the product C

F

× R

ω

.

We identify a filter F on a countable set T with a subset of a Cantor set 2

T

. As shown in [DMM, Lemma 4.2] the exact Borel class of c

F

is entirely determined by that of F in 2

T

. Here we try to recover this result for the space C

F

. The first result shows that Borel (projective) classes of C

F

and C

F

are not lower than that of F .

3.3. Proposition. Let F be a filter on a countable set T . For every countable ordinal α and n ∈ ω, we have:

(a) if C

F

∈ M

α

, then F ∈ M

α

, (b) if C

F

∈ A

α

, then F ∈ A

α

, (c) if C

F

∈ P

n

, then F ∈ P

n

.

In (a)–(c), the space C

F

can be replaced by C

F

provided F is not an ultra- filter.

P r o o f. We may assume T = ω. Consider

Z = {f ∈ C

F

| ∀(n ∈ ω) (f (n) = 0 or f (n) = n + 1)},

a closed subset of C

F

. The map (x

n

) → ((n + 1)(1 − x

n

)) embeds 2

ω

in R

ω

and sends F onto Z. Thus, the C

F

-part of our assertion follows.

Assume that F is not an ultrafilter on ω (see 2.11). There exists a subset M ⊂ ω such that neither M nor N = ω \ M belongs to F . Consider the filters

G = {A ∩ M | A ∈ F } and H = {A ∩ H | A ∈ F } induced by F on M and N , respectively. The sets

Y

1

= {f ∈ C

F

∩ {0, 1}

ω

| f |N = 0}, Y

2

= {f ∈ C

F

∩ {0, 1}

ω

| f |M = 0}

are closed subsets of C

F

. It is clear that G and H are homeomorphic to Y

1

and Y

2

, respectively. Finally, since F can be identified with the product G × H, our assertion follows.

Here is our counterpart of [DMM, Lemma 4.2] for spaces C

F

.

3.4. Proposition. Let F be a filter on ω. For every countable ordinal

α ≥ 1 and n ∈ ω, we have:

(10)

(a) if F ∈ A

α

, then C

F

∈ M

α+1

,

(b) if F ∈ M

α

, then C

F

∈ M

α+1

∩ A

α+1

(more exactly, C

F

is a differ- ence of two sets belonging to M

α

),

(c) if F ∈ P

n

, then C

F

∈ P

n

.

P r o o f. First we provide an argument which shows (a) and (c). Then we adapt this argument to check that whenever F ∈ M

α

then C

F

∩ [0, 1]

ω

M

α

. Finally, since C

F

is homeomorphic to

{f ∈ C

F

| ∀(n ∈ ω) (f (n) ∈ (0, 1) and lim

F

f (n) ∈ (0, 1))}

= (C

F

∩ [0, 1]

ω

) ∩ (0, 1)

ω

\ (c

F

∪ (1 + c

F

)), the space C

F

is a difference of two sets belonging to M

α

(by [DMM, Lem- ma 4.2], c

F

and hence 1 + c

F

= {(x

n

+ 1) ∈ R

ω

| (x

n

) ∈ c

F

} belong to M

α

).

Assume F ∈ A

α

(resp., F ∈ P

n

). For n ∈ ω and k ∈ Z, write T

n,k

=

 2k

2n + 2 , 2k + 1 2n + 2

 . Set T

n

= S

k∈Z

T

n,k

. For m ∈ N and l ∈ Z, define S

m,l,n

= [

k

 T

n,k

dist

 l m , T

n,k



1 m

 .

Let %

m,l

: Q

n∈ω

T

n

→ 2

ω

be given by

%

m,l

(f )(n) =

 1 if f (n) ∈ S

m,l,n

, 0 otherwise, for f ∈ Q

n∈ω

T

n

. One can check that %

m,l

is continuous. We claim that

(1) C

F

Y

n∈ω

T

n

=

\

m=1

[

l∈Z

%

−1m,l

(F ).

(If f = (f (n)) ∈ Q

n∈ω

T

n

and there exists x ∈ R such that for all ε > 0 we have f

−1

((x − ε, x + ε)) ∈ F , then for every m ≥ 1 one can find l ∈ Z so that |x − l/m| ≤ 1/(2m) and check that {n | f (n) ∈ S

m,l,n

} ∈ F ; this shows %

m,l

(f ) ∈ F . Conversely, if for every m ≥ 1 one can find l ∈ Z so that {n | f (n) ∈ S

m,l,n

} ∈ F , then there exists A ∈ F so that whenever i, j ∈ A then |f (i) − f (j)| < 4/m; this implies f ∈ C

F

.)

Pick a map ψ

n

: T

n

→ R that transforms T

n,k

affinely onto 

2k

2n+2

,

2k+22n+2

 , k ∈ Z. Letting ψ = Q

n∈ω

ψ

n

: Q

n∈ω

T

n

→ R

ω

we see that ψ is a perfect map and that

(2) C

F

Y

n∈ω

T

n

= ψ

−1

(C

F

).

Applying (1), C

F

Q

n∈ω

T

n

∈ M

α+1

(resp., C

F

Q

n∈ω

T

n

∈ P

n

). By (2)

and a result of Saint Raymond [SR1], C

F

∈ M

α+1

(resp., C

F

∈ P

n

).

(11)

Now, let F ∈ M

α

. We must show that C

F

∩ [0, 1]

ω

∈ M

α

. Using the sets T

n,k

we define

T

n

=

n−1

[

k=0

T

n,k

.

With these T

n

, as previously, define for m ∈ N and l ∈ {0, . . . , m} the sets S

m,l,n

and maps %

m,l

. One can check

(1)

0

C

F

Y

n∈ω

T

n

=

\

m=1

[

m l=0

%

−1m,l

(F ).

Let ψ

n

: T

n

→ [0, 1] be a map such that T

n,k

is affinely transformed onto



2k

2n+2

,

2n+22k+2



. Letting ψ = Q

n∈ω

ψ

n

: Q

n∈ω

T

n

→ [0, 1]

ω

, we have

(2)

0

C

F

Y

n∈ω

T

n

= ψ

−1

(C

F

∩ [0, 1]

ω

).

Using (1)

0

, C

F

Q

n∈ω

T

n

∈ M

α

. As above, by (2)

0

and a result of Saint Raymond [SR1], C

F

∩ [0, 1]

ω

∈ M

α

.

3.5. Question. Let F ∈ M

α

be a filter on ω. Is C

F

∈ M

α

?

Let F be a filter on ω. Identify the space C

F

with C

ω

(N

F

). Using this identification, let ` : C

F

→ R be given by `(f ) = f (∞). We see that ` is well defined and can be viewed as `(f ) = lim

F

f (n).

3.6. Proposition. For a filter F ∈ A

α

∪ M

α

, and a countable ordinal α, α ≥ 1, ` : C

F

→ R is Borel of class α.

P r o o f. Let U ⊆ R be an open set. We must show that `

−1

(U ) ∈ A

α

(C

F

).

We shall use some of the notation employed in the proof of 3.4. For n ∈ ω and m ∈ N, let

P

n,m

= [

{T

n,k

| ∀(t ∈ T

n,k

) (dist(t, R \ U ) > 1/m)}.

Recall that T

n

= S

k∈Z

T

n,k

and define ζ

m

: Q

n∈ω

T

n

→ {0, 1}

ω

by letting for f ∈ Q

n∈ω

T

n

,

ζ

m

(f )(n) =

n 1 if f (n) ∈ P

n,m

, 0 otherwise.

Clearly, ζ

m

is continuous, m ≥ 1. Let ψ : Q

n∈ω

T

n

→ R

ω

be that of the proof of 3.4.

Suppose F ∈ A

α

. Consider S = S

m=1

ζ

m−1

(F ). We see that S ∈ A

α

(S ∈ A

1

( Q

n∈ω

T

n

) for α = 1). We claim that ψ

−1

(ψ(S)) = S. Let f, g ∈ Q

n∈ω

T

n

(12)

be such that g ∈ S

m=1

ζ

m−1

(F ) and ψ(f ) = ψ(g). Since ψ(f ) = ψ(g), we have |g(n) − f (n)| < 1/n. Take m

0

such that g ∈ ζ

m−10

(F ). If n > 2m

0

and g(n) ∈ P

n,m0

, then f (n) ∈ P

n,2m0

. It follows that ζ

2m0

(f ) ⊃ ζ

m0

(g) \ {0, 1, . . . , 2m

0

}; and hence ζ

2m0

(f ) ∈ F . This shows that f ∈ ζ

2m−10

(F ) ⊂ S.

Suppose F ∈ M

α

. Let J = {A ⊂ ω | ω \ A ∈ F } be the dual ideal of F ; J is homeomorphic to F . Consider T = ( Q

n∈ω

T

n

) \ T

m=1

ζ

n−1

(J ). We see that T ∈ A

α

. We claim that ψ

−1

(ψ(T )) = T . Let f, g ∈ Q

n∈ω

T

n

be such that f 6∈ T

m=1

ζ

m−1

(J ) and ψ(f ) = ψ(g). Take m

0

such that f 6∈ ζ

m−10

(J ).

If n > 2m

0

and f (n) ∈ P

n,m0

, then g(n) ∈ P

n,2m0

. As previously, it follows that ζ

2m0

(g) 6∈ J ; hence g ∈ T .

We now claim that

(1) C

F

∩ S = C

F

∩ T =  Y

n∈ω

T

n



∩ `

−1

(U ).

Namely, we have f ∈ S (resp., f ∈ T ) if and only if there exists m ≥ 1 such that f ∈ ζ

m−1

(F ) (resp., f 6∈ ζ

m−1

(J )). Suppose f ∈ ( Q

n∈ω

T

n

) ∩ `

−1

(U ) and f (∞) = x ∈ U . Let ε = dist(x, R \ U ). For m, n > 4/ε we have (x − ε/2, x + ε/2) ∩ T

n

⊆ P

n,m

. It follows that f ∈ ζ

m−1

(F ) and hence f 6∈ ζ

m−1

(J ). Suppose now that f ∈ C

F

and f ∈ ζ

m−1

(F ). Since f 6∈ ζ

m−1

(J ) the set R = {n | f (n) ∈ P

n,m

} is not in J . Take x 6∈ U . Then for every n ≥ 1, (x − 1/(2m), x + 1/(2m)) ∩ P

n,m

= ∅. Therefore for Q = {n | f (n) ∈ (x − 1/(2m), x + 1/(2m))} we have R ∩ Q = ∅. Since R 6∈ J , we have Q 6∈ F . It follows that f (∞) 6= x, so f (∞) ∈ U .

Since lim

n

(f (n)−ψ(f )(n)) = 0, one sees that lim

F

f (n) = lim

F

ψ(f )(n);

and consequently

`

−1

(U ) = ψ  Y

n∈ω

T

n



∩ `

−1

(U )

 .

This together with (1) and the fact that ψ

−1

(C

F

) = C

F

Q

n∈ω

T

n

yields

`

−1

(U ) = ψ(C

F

∩ S) = C

F

∩ ψ(S),

`

−1

(U ) = ψ(C

F

∩ T ) = C

F

∩ ψ(T ).

The facts that ψ

−1

(ψ(S)) = S and ψ

−1

(ψ(T )) = T together with a result of Saint Raymond [SR1] show that, under our assumption, C

F

∩ ϕ(S) and C

F

∩ ϕ(T ) belong to A

α

(C

F

).

The following is a partial answer to Question 3.5.

3.7. Corollary. For n ∈ ω, let F

n

be a filter on ω with F

n

S

β<α

A

β

, α ≥ 1. Then for the filter F = Q

n∈ω

F

n

on ω × ω, we have C

F

∈ M

α

. P r o o f. We obviously have

F = {A ⊂ ω × ω | ∀(n ∈ ω) ({m | (m, n) ∈ A} ∈ F

n

)}.

(13)

Moreover, for f = (f (m, n)) ∈ R

ω×ω

, f ∈ C

F

if and only if f (·, n) ∈ C

Fn

, n ∈ ω, and lim

Fn

f (·, n) = lim

Fk

f (·, k) for n, k ∈ ω. Now our assertion follows by application of 3.4 and 3.6.

The assertion of Proposition 3.9 below shows that the result of [DDM, Lemma 4.2] is fully recovered for the spaces C

F

. The proof of 3.9 requires a particular case of the following general fact.

3.8. Proposition. Let X be a separable metrizable space such that X = S

n=1

X

n

, X

n

∈ M

α

, α ≥ 2 and X

n

∈ A

β

(X), where β < α. Then X ∈ M

α

. P r o o f. Let Y be a metrizable compactification of X and let Y

n

∈ A

β

be such that Y

n

∩ X = X

n

. Consider Z = S

n=1

Y

n

∈ A

β

⊆ M

α

. We have Y

n

\X

n

∈ A

α

; hence, S

n=1

(Y

n

\X

n

) ∈ A

α

and X = Z\ S

n=1

(Y

n

\X

n

) ∈ M

α

.

3.9. Proposition. Let F be a filter on ω, α be a countable ordinal, α ≥ 1, and let n ∈ ω. We have:

(a) if F ∈ A

α

\ M

α

, then C

F

∈ M

α+1

\ A

α+1

, (b) if F ∈ M

α

\ A

α

, then C

F

∈ M

α

\ A

α

, (c) if F ∈ M

α

∩ A

α

\ S

β<α

(A

β

∪ M

β

), then C

F

∈ M

α

\ A

α

, (d) if F ∈ P

n

, then C

F

∈ P

n

.

P r o o f. The proof of the second part of 3.4 yields that whenever F ∈ M

α

, C

F

∩ [−n, n]

ω

∈ M

α

for n ≥ 1. Since C

F

= S

n=1

(C

F

∩ [−n, n]

ω

) and each C

F

∩ [−n, n]

ω

is closed in C

F

, it follows from 3.8 that C

F

M

α

(observe that here α ≥ 2 since there are no filters of class M

1

). If additionally F 6∈ A

α

then, by 3.3, C

F

∈ M

α

\A

α

; hence (b) follows. Assume F ∈ M

α

∩A

α

\ S

β<α

(A

β

∪M

β

). Consider the decomposition F = G×H of F into filters G and H described in the proof of 3.3 (obviously, being Borel, F is not an ultrafilter). We may assume that G ∈ M

α

∩A

α

\ S

β<α

M

β

(if not, H has this property). Recall that Σ = {(x

n

) ∈ R

ω

| (x

n

) is bounded}. Applying [DMM, Lemma 4.2(3)], we find that c

G

∈ M

α

\ A

α

. Since c

G

= c

G

∩ Σ and c

G

is homeomorphic to c

G

∩ (−1, 1)

ω

, we conclude that c

G

∈ M

α

\ A

α

. Finally, since C

F

contains c

G

as a closed set, it follows that C

F

∈ M

α

\ A

α

; this shows (c).

To get (a), suppose F ∈ A

α

\ M

α

. Since C

F

= C

F

∩ Σ, 3.4(a) yields C

F

∈ M

α+1

. Considering, as previously, F = G × H, we may assume G ∈ A

α

\ M

α

. By [DDM, Lemma 4.2(4)], c

G

∈ M

α+1

\ A

α+1

. As before, this implies that c

G

∈ M

α+1

\ A

α+1

and consequently C

F

∈ M

α+1

\ A

α+1

.

The assertion (d) follows from 3.4(c) and the fact that C

F

= C

F

∩ Σ.

We now provide a counterpart of [DMM, Lemma 4.3]. Let X be a count-

able space. For every accumulation point a of X we consider the filter F

a

(14)

on X \ {a} consisting of all neighborhoods of a; hence F

a

= {Y ∈ 2

X\{a}

| a ∈ Int(Y ∪ {a})}.

3.10. Lemma. Let X be a countable space and A ⊆ X be a dense set.

If there exists a countable ordinal α, α ≥ 1 (resp., an integer n ∈ ω) such that for every accumulation point a ∈ X the filter F

a

is in A

α

∪ M

α

(resp., F

a

∈ P

n

), then C

A

(X) ∈ M

α+1

(resp., C

A

(X) ∈ P

n

).

P r o o f (cf. [DMM, Lemma 4.3]). Let a be an accumulation point of X.

Define a filter on A by letting

G

a

= {Y ∩ A | Y ∈ F

a

}.

The filter G

a

is homeomorphic to

{Y ∈ F

a

| X \ (A ∪ {a}) ⊆ Y },

a closed subset of F

a

. Therefore G

a

∈ A

a

∪ M

α

(resp., G

a

∈ P

n

). Let X

a

be the space A ∪ {a} topologized by isolating the points of A \ {a} and using the family {Y ∪ {a} | Y ∈ G

a

} as a neighborhood base at a (it may happen that a ∈ A). Then either C

A

(X

a

) is isomorphic to c

Ga

(in case a ∈ A), or else C

A

(X

α

) is isomorphic to C

Gα

(in case a 6∈ A). From Proposition 3.4 and [DMM, Lemma 4.2] (see also [CDM, Corollary 5.3(d)]) it follows that in both cases C

A

(X

a

) ∈ M

α+1

(resp., C

A

(X

a

) ∈ P

n

). Now, 3.10 is a consequence of the following observation:

C

A

(X) = \

{C

A

(X

a

) | a is an accumulation point of X}.

3.11. R e m a r k. Let X

α

be the space from Proposition 2.6. Then C

p

(X

α

)

∈ F

σδ

. Moreover, according to Lemma 3.10, there exists a ∈ X

α

such that F

a

6∈ S

β<α

A

β

∪ M

β

; in fact, one can show that a = x

α

has this prop- erty. (As shown in [DMM, Corollary 3.6] the filters F

a

are analytic provided C

p

(X) is analytic.) Observe that the filter F

a

has a base which is of the F

σδ

-type. Namely, the filter base {Y ⊂ X \ {a} | Y ∪ {a} is a clopen subset of X containing a} is homeomorphic to

{f ∈ C

p

(X

α

) ∩ {0, 1}

Xα

| f (a) = 1}, a closed subset of C

p

(X

α

).

4. Z

σ

-property of C

A

(X). We recall that a closed subset A of an absolute neighborhood retract M is a Z-set if every map f : K → M of a compactum K into M can be approximated by maps f : K → M \ A.

A space which is a countable union of its own Z-sets is called a Z

σ

-space.

Obviously, every Z

σ

-space is of the first category. It is a well-known fact

that a dense convex subset of a convex Z

σ

-space is itself a Z

σ

-space. Since

C

A

(X) is dense in R

A

and since Σ = {(x

n

) ∈ R

ω

| (x

n

) is bounded} is a

Z

σ

-space, we have:

(15)

4.1. Lemma. Let X be a space and let A be a countable dense subset of X.

(a) The space C

A

(X) is a Z

σ

-space.

(b) If X is compact, then C

A

(X) is a Z

σ

-space.

4.2. Proposition. Let X be a countable nondiscrete space and let A be a dense subset of X. If C

A

(X) is analytic, then C

A

(X) and C

p

(X) are Z

σ

-spaces.

Let us recall that a filter F on a countable set T is of the first category if F belongs to the σ-field generated by the open sets and the first category sets of 2

T

. We need the following fact.

4.3. Lemma. Let F be a first category filter on a countable set T . Then for every 0 < r ≤ ∞ the space C

F

∩ [−r, r]

ω

is a Z

σ

-space.

P r o o f. By a result of Talagrand [Ta, Theorem 2.1] there exists a se- quence of pairwise disjoint finite sets A

n

⊂ T such that every A ∈ F meets all but finitely many A

n

, n ∈ N.

For finite r, let

X

n

= {f ∈ C

F

∩ [−r, r]

ω

| ∀(k > n)∃(m ∈ A

k

) (|f (m)| ≤ 2r/3)}

and

Y

n

= {f ∈ C

F

∩ [−r, r]

ω

| ∀(k > n)∃(m ∈ A

k

) (|f (m)| ≥ r/3)}.

An argument of the proof of [DMM, Proposition 3.3] shows that each X

n

and Y

n

, n ≥ 1, is a Z-set. Moreover, C

F

∩ [−r, r]

ω

= S

n=1

X

n

∪ Y

n

. For r = ∞, let

X

n,l

= {f ∈ C

F

| ∀(k > n)∃(m ∈ A

k

) (|f (m)| ≤ l)}.

As previously, each X

n,l

is a Z-set in C

F

and C

F

= S

n,l=1

X

n,l

.

P r o o f o f 4.2. 1

o

Assume A has an accumulation point a ∈ A. Consider E = {f ∈ C

A

(X) ∩ {0, 1}

A

| f (a) = 1},

a closed subset of C

A

(X). The space E can be identified with F

a

= {U ∩A | U is clopen and a ∈ U }. Let F be the filter on A \ {a} generated by F

a

, i.e.,

F = {B ⊂ A \ {a} | ∃(f ∈ E) (f

−1

({1}) ⊂ B ∪ {a})}.

By an argument of [DMM, Corollary 3.6], F is an analytic filter and con- sequently it belongs to the σ-field generated by the open sets and the first category sets of 2

A\{a}

. By 4.3, C

F

is a Z

σ

-space. Since C

A

(X) is a dense linear subspace of C

F

× R ⊂ R

A\{a}

× R = R

A

, C

A

(X) is a Z

σ

-space.

2

o

Assume A is discrete. For every x ∈ X \A, let F

x

= {U ∩A | x ∈ Int U } be a filter of neighborhoods of x.

Claim. There exists x

0

∈ X \ A such that F

x0

is of the first category.

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

Third European Set Theory Conference Edinburgh,

[27] —, Nonlinear boundary value problems at resonance for differential equations in Banach spaces, preprint..

Conversely, for any finite subset S of the plane, or for any finite family S of disjoint plane C-curves we construct an automorphism of the plane for which the set of fixed points

Generic and dense chaos have been characterized respectively in [Sn1] and [Sn2], and it is known that dense chaos need not imply generic chaos (cf.. In [Sn3], the definitions of

This paper considers the results of Kunen [3] regard- ing intersection topologies with respect to the real line and the countable ordinals, and demonstrates how they may be

In the sequel we shall denote by X 0 the family of all countable subsets of X.. to 0 in the

The paper deals with the theory of Orlicz spaces of functions with values in separable, linear topological spaces... Separability of Orlicz

The main result of the present paper is Theorem 3, which is a generalization of the C 0 -closing lemma to the case of a not necessarily compact manifold.. Moreover, under