• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Random walks are completely determined by their trace on the positive half-line

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Share "Random walks are completely determined by their trace on the positive half-line"

Copied!
99
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

Random walks

are completely determined by their trace

on the positive half-line

Mateusz Kwa±nicki

Wrocªaw University of Science and Technology mateusz.kwasnicki@pwr.edu.pl

Guanajuato, Nov 29, 2017

(2)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Main Theorem

Random walks

are completely determined by their trace

on the positive half-line

(3)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A few remarks

• Acknowledgement: Loïc Chaumont from Angers, France.

• SPA 2017 conference

(The 39th Conference on Stochastic Processes and their Applications, Moscow, Jul 2428, 2017)

Loïc Chaumont, Ron Doney

On distributions determined by their upward, space-time WienerHopf factor

arXiv:1702.00067 V. Vigon

Simpliez vos Lévy en titillant la factorisation de WienerHopf

PhD thesis, INSA de Rouen, 2001

(4)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A few remarks

• Acknowledgement: Loïc Chaumont from Angers, France.

• SPA 2017 conference

(The 39th Conference on Stochastic Processes and their Applications, Moscow, Jul 2428, 2017)

Loïc Chaumont, Ron Doney

On distributions determined by their upward, space-time WienerHopf factor

arXiv:1702.00067 V. Vigon

Simpliez vos Lévy en titillant la factorisation de WienerHopf

PhD thesis, INSA de Rouen, 2001

(5)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A few remarks

• Acknowledgement: Loïc Chaumont from Angers, France.

• SPA 2017 conference

(The 39th Conference on Stochastic Processes and their Applications, Moscow, Jul 2428, 2017)

Loïc Chaumont, Ron Doney

On distributions determined by their upward, space-time WienerHopf factor

arXiv:1702.00067

V. Vigon

Simpliez vos Lévy en titillant la factorisation de WienerHopf

PhD thesis, INSA de Rouen, 2001

(6)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A few remarks

• Acknowledgement: Loïc Chaumont from Angers, France.

• SPA 2017 conference

(The 39th Conference on Stochastic Processes and their Applications, Moscow, Jul 2428, 2017)

Loïc Chaumont, Ron Doney

On distributions determined by their upward, space-time WienerHopf factor

arXiv:1702.00067 V. Vigon

Simpliez vos Lévy en titillant la factorisation de WienerHopf

PhD thesis, INSA de Rouen, 2001

(7)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Random walks

• Arandom walk Xn is a sequence of partial sums of i.i.d.

random variables:

Xn = ∆X1+ ∆X2 + . . . + ∆Xn,

where ∆X1, ∆X2, . . . are independent and identically distributed on R.

• We say that a random walk Xn is non-trivial if P(X1 >0) 6= 0.

• We write A= Bd if P(A > t) = P(B > t) for all t ∈ R.

• Of course if X1 d

= Y1, then Xn d

= Yn for all n = 1, 2, . . .; in this case we say that Xn and Yn are identical.

(8)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Random walks

• Arandom walk Xn is a sequence of partial sums of i.i.d.

random variables:

Xn = ∆X1+ ∆X2 + . . . + ∆Xn,

where ∆X1, ∆X2, . . . are independent and identically distributed on R.

• We say that a random walk Xn is non-trivial if P(X1 >0) 6= 0.

• We write A= Bd if P(A > t) = P(B > t) for all t ∈ R.

• Of course if X1 d

= Y1, then Xn d

= Yn for all n = 1, 2, . . .; in this case we say that Xn and Yn are identical.

(9)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Random walks

• Arandom walk Xn is a sequence of partial sums of i.i.d.

random variables:

Xn = ∆X1+ ∆X2 + . . . + ∆Xn,

where ∆X1, ∆X2, . . . are independent and identically distributed on R.

• We say that a random walk Xn is non-trivial if P(X1 >0) 6= 0.

• We write A= Bd if P(A > t) = P(B > t) for all t ∈ R.

• Of course if X1 d

= Y1, then Xn d

= Yn for all n = 1, 2, . . .; in this case we say that Xn and Yn are identical.

(10)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Random walks

• Arandom walk Xn is a sequence of partial sums of i.i.d.

random variables:

Xn = ∆X1+ ∆X2 + . . . + ∆Xn,

where ∆X1, ∆X2, . . . are independent and identically distributed on R.

• We say that a random walk Xn is non-trivial if P(X1 >0) 6= 0.

• We write A= Bd if P(A > t) = P(B > t) for all t ∈ R.

• Of course if X1 d

= Y1, then Xn d

= Yn for all n = 1, 2, . . .;

in this case we say that Xn and Yn are identical.

(11)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Main theorem

Theorem

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and P(Xn> t) = P(Yn > t)

for all n = 1, 2, . . . and all t ∈(0, ∞), then the same is true for all t ∈R(that is, Xn and Yn are identical).

• This was proved by Chaumont and Doney under additional conditions on Xn and Yn:

I if X1 has exponential moments; or

I if P(X1 > t) is completely monotone on (0, ∞); or

I if X1 has analytic density function on (0, ∞).

• This covers a majority of interesting examples.

• It is often enough to take n = 1, 2 in the assumption.

(12)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Main theorem

Theorem

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and P(Xn> t) = P(Yn > t)

for all n = 1, 2, . . . and all t ∈(0, ∞), then the same is true for all t ∈R(that is, Xn and Yn are identical).

• This was proved by Chaumont and Doney under additional conditions on Xn and Yn:

I if X1 has exponential moments; or

I if P(X1 > t) is completely monotone on (0, ∞); or

I if X1 has analytic density function on (0, ∞).

• This covers a majority of interesting examples.

• It is often enough to take n = 1, 2 in the assumption.

(13)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Main theorem

Theorem

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and P(Xn> t) = P(Yn > t)

for all n = 1, 2, . . . and all t ∈(0, ∞), then the same is true for all t ∈R(that is, Xn and Yn are identical).

• This was proved by Chaumont and Doney under additional conditions on Xn and Yn:

I if X1 has exponential moments; or

I if P(X1 > t) is completely monotone on (0, ∞); or

I if X1 has analytic density function on (0, ∞).

• This covers a majority of interesting examples.

• It is often enough to take n = 1, 2 in the assumption.

(14)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Main theorem

Theorem

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and P(Xn> t) = P(Yn > t)

for all n = 1, 2, . . . and all t ∈(0, ∞), then the same is true for all t ∈R(that is, Xn and Yn are identical).

• This was proved by Chaumont and Doney under additional conditions on Xn and Yn:

I if X1 has exponential moments; or

I if P(X1 > t) is completely monotone on (0, ∞); or

I if X1 has analytic density function on (0, ∞).

• This covers a majority of interesting examples.

• It is often enough to take n = 1, 2 in the assumption.

(15)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Simple reformulation

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and max{0, Xn}=d max{0, Yn} for all n = 1, 2, . . ., then

Xn= Yd n for all n = 1, 2, . . .

(16)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some uctuation theory

• Dene Xn =max{0, X1, X2, . . . , Xn}.

• Spitzer's formula: if |w| < 1 and Im z > 0, then

X

n=0

E exp(izXn)wn=exp

 X

n=0

E exp(iz max{0, Xn})

n wn

 .

• Knowing the distributions of Xn is thus equivalent to knowing the distributions of max{0, Xn}.

(17)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some uctuation theory

• Dene Xn =max{0, X1, X2, . . . , Xn}.

• Spitzer's formula: if |w| < 1 and Im z > 0, then

X

n=0

E exp(izXn)wn=exp

 X

n=0

E exp(iz max{0, Xn})

n wn

 .

• Knowing the distributions of Xn is thus equivalent to knowing the distributions of max{0, Xn}.

(18)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some uctuation theory

• Dene Xn =max{0, X1, X2, . . . , Xn}.

• Spitzer's formula: if |w| < 1 and Im z > 0, then

X

n=0

E exp(izXn)wn=exp

 X

n=0

E exp(iz max{0, Xn})

n wn

 .

• Knowing the distributions of Xn is thus equivalent to knowing the distributions of max{0, Xn}.

(19)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Another reformulation

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks, and Xn = Yd n

for all n = 1, 2, . . ., then

Xn= Yd n for all n = 1, 2, . . .

(20)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some more uctuation theory

• Let N be the smallest number n such that Xn>0

(the rst ladder time).

• Let H be the the value of Xn for n = N

(the rst ladder height).

• Knowing the joint distribution of N and H, one can reconstruct the distributions of Xn for n = 1, 2, . . .

• The characteristic function of (N, H) is essentially the upward space-time WienerHopf factor.

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks with equal upward space-time WienerHopf factors, then Xnand Yn are identical.

(21)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some more uctuation theory

• Let N be the smallest number n such that Xn>0

(the rst ladder time).

• Let H be the the value of Xn for n = N

(the rst ladder height).

• Knowing the joint distribution of N and H, one can reconstruct the distributions of Xn for n = 1, 2, . . .

• The characteristic function of (N, H) is essentially the upward space-time WienerHopf factor.

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks with equal upward space-time WienerHopf factors, then Xnand Yn are identical.

(22)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some more uctuation theory

• Let N be the smallest number n such that Xn>0

(the rst ladder time).

• Let H be the the value of Xn for n = N

(the rst ladder height).

• Knowing the joint distribution of N and H, one can reconstruct the distributions of Xn for n = 1, 2, . . .

• The characteristic function of (N, H) is essentially the upward space-time WienerHopf factor.

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks with equal upward space-time WienerHopf factors, then Xnand Yn are identical.

(23)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some more uctuation theory

• Let N be the smallest number n such that Xn>0

(the rst ladder time).

• Let H be the the value of Xn for n = N

(the rst ladder height).

• Knowing the joint distribution of N and H, one can reconstruct the distributions of Xn for n = 1, 2, . . .

• The characteristic function of (N, H) is essentially the upward space-time WienerHopf factor.

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks with equal upward space-time WienerHopf factors, then Xnand Yn are identical.

(24)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Some more uctuation theory

• Let N be the smallest number n such that Xn>0

(the rst ladder time).

• Let H be the the value of Xn for n = N

(the rst ladder height).

• Knowing the joint distribution of N and H, one can reconstruct the distributions of Xn for n = 1, 2, . . .

• The characteristic function of (N, H) is essentially the upward space-time WienerHopf factor.

Theorem (equivalent version)

If Xn and Yn are non-trivial random walks with equal upward space-time WienerHopf factors, then Xnand Yn are identical.

(25)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Lévy processes

• A Lévy process is, in some sense, a random walk in continuous time.

• Formally, Xt is a Lévy process if it has independent and stationary increments, and càdlàg paths.

Corollary

If Xt and Yt are non-trivial Lévy processes, and max{0, Xt}=d max{0, Yt}

(or Xt d

= Yt)

for all t > 0, then

Xt = Yd t for all t > 0.

• Conjectured by Vigon, proved under extra assumptions by Chaumont and Doney

(26)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Lévy processes

• A Lévy process is, in some sense, a random walk in continuous time.

• Formally, Xt is a Lévy process if it has independent and stationary increments, and càdlàg paths.

Corollary

If Xt and Yt are non-trivial Lévy processes, and max{0, Xt}=d max{0, Yt}

(or Xt d

= Yt)

for all t > 0, then

Xt = Yd t for all t > 0.

• Conjectured by Vigon, proved under extra assumptions by Chaumont and Doney

(27)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Lévy processes

• A Lévy process is, in some sense, a random walk in continuous time.

• Formally, Xt is a Lévy process if it has independent and stationary increments, and càdlàg paths.

Corollary

If Xt and Yt are non-trivial Lévy processes, and max{0, Xt}=d max{0, Yt}

(or Xt d

= Yt)

for all t > 0, then

Xt = Yd t for all t > 0.

• Conjectured by Vigon, proved under extra assumptions by Chaumont and Doney

(28)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Lévy processes

• A Lévy process is, in some sense, a random walk in continuous time.

• Formally, Xt is a Lévy process if it has independent and stationary increments, and càdlàg paths.

Corollary

If Xt and Yt are non-trivial Lévy processes, and max{0, Xt}=d max{0, Yt} (or Xt d

= Yt) for all t > 0, then

Xt = Yd t for all t > 0.

• Conjectured by Vigon, proved under extra assumptions by Chaumont and Doney

(29)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Lévy processes

• A Lévy process is, in some sense, a random walk in continuous time.

• Formally, Xt is a Lévy process if it has independent and stationary increments, and càdlàg paths.

Corollary

If Xt and Yt are non-trivial Lévy processes, and max{0, Xt}=d max{0, Yt} (or Xt d

= Yt) for all t > 0, then

Xt = Yd t for all t > 0.

• Conjectured by Vigon, proved under extra assumptions by Chaumont and Doney

(30)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A variant for measures

• All measures below are nite signed Borel measures on R.

• The convolution of measures µ and ν is given by (µ ∗ ν)(A) =

Z

R

µ(A − x )ν(dx ). Convolutive powers of µ are denoted by µn.

• We say that a measure µ isnon-trivial if the restriction of µto (0, ∞) is a non-zero measure.

Theorem (extended version)

If µ and ν are non-trivial measures and µn(A) = νn(A)

for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . ., then µ = ν.

(31)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A variant for measures

• All measures below are nite signed Borel measures on R.

• The convolution of measures µ and ν is given by (µ ∗ ν)(A) =

Z

R

µ(A − x )ν(dx ).

Convolutive powers of µ are denoted by µn.

• We say that a measure µ isnon-trivial if the restriction of µto (0, ∞) is a non-zero measure.

Theorem (extended version)

If µ and ν are non-trivial measures and µn(A) = νn(A)

for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . ., then µ = ν.

(32)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A variant for measures

• All measures below are nite signed Borel measures on R.

• The convolution of measures µ and ν is given by (µ ∗ ν)(A) =

Z

R

µ(A − x )ν(dx ).

Convolutive powers of µ are denoted by µn.

• We say that a measure µ isnon-trivial if the restriction of µto (0, ∞) is a non-zero measure.

Theorem (extended version)

If µ and ν are non-trivial measures and µn(A) = νn(A)

for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . ., then µ = ν.

(33)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

A variant for measures

• All measures below are nite signed Borel measures on R.

• The convolution of measures µ and ν is given by (µ ∗ ν)(A) =

Z

R

µ(A − x )ν(dx ).

Convolutive powers of µ are denoted by µn.

• We say that a measure µ isnon-trivial if the restriction of µto (0, ∞) is a non-zero measure.

Theorem (extended version)

If µ and ν are non-trivial measures and µn(A) = νn(A)

for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . ., then µ = ν.

(34)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Change of notation

• We assume that

µn(A) = νn(A) for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . .

• Considering n = 1, we see that the restrictions of µ and ν to (0, ∞) agree.

• Denote:

α = 1(0,∞)µ = 1(0,∞)µ, β = 1(−∞,0]µ,

γ = 1(−∞,0]ν.

• Now µ = α + β and ν = α + γ.

(35)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Change of notation

• We assume that

µn(A) = νn(A) for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . .

• Considering n = 1, we see that the restrictions of µ and ν to (0, ∞) agree.

• Denote:

α = 1(0,∞)µ = 1(0,∞)µ, β = 1(−∞,0]µ,

γ = 1(−∞,0]ν.

• Now µ = α + β and ν = α + γ.

(36)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Change of notation

• We assume that

µn(A) = νn(A) for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . .

• Considering n = 1, we see that the restrictions of µ and ν to (0, ∞) agree.

• Denote:

α = 1(0,∞)µ = 1(0,∞)µ, β = 1(−∞,0]µ,

γ = 1(−∞,0]ν.

• Now µ = α + β and ν = α + γ.

(37)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Change of notation

• We assume that

µn(A) = νn(A) for all Borel A ⊆ (0, ∞) and n = 1, 2, . . .

• Considering n = 1, we see that the restrictions of µ and ν to (0, ∞) agree.

• Denote:

α = 1(0,∞)µ = 1(0,∞)µ, β = 1(−∞,0]µ,

γ = 1(−∞,0]ν.

• Now µ = α + β and ν = α + γ.

(38)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Idea of the proof

• α is a non-zero measure concentrated on (0, ∞), β and γ are concentrated on (−∞, 0].

• The proof consists of two steps:

1(0,∞)(α + β)n = 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w

 (simple algebra)

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . .

w w

 (complex analysis) β = γ

.

(39)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Idea of the proof

• α is a non-zero measure concentrated on (0, ∞), β and γ are concentrated on (−∞, 0].

• The proof consists of two steps:

1(0,∞)(α + β)n= 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w

 (simple algebra)

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . .

w w

 (complex analysis) β = γ

.

(40)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

Idea of the proof

• α is a non-zero measure concentrated on (0, ∞), β and γ are concentrated on (−∞, 0].

• The proof consists of two steps:

1(0,∞)(α + β)n= 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w

 (simple algebra)

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . . w

w

 (complex analysis) β = γ.

(41)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)(α + β)n= 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w



1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for all n = 0, 1, . . . and k = 1, 2, . . .

• Induction with respect to n.

• For n = 0:

1(0,∞)k) = 0 = 1(0,∞)k).

(42)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)(α + β)n= 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w



1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for all n = 0, 1, . . . and k = 1, 2, . . .

• Induction with respect to n.

• For n = 0:

1(0,∞)k) = 0 = 1(0,∞)k).

(43)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)(α + β)n= 1(0,∞)(α + γ)n for all n = 1, 2, . . . w

w



1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for all n = 0, 1, . . . and k = 1, 2, . . .

• Induction with respect to n.

• For n = 0:

1(0,∞)k) = 0 = 1(0,∞)k).

(44)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(45)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN ∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j ∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(46)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN ∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j ∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(47)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN ∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j ∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(48)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN ∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j ∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(49)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)n∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γk)for n = 0, 1, . . . , N − 1 and k = 1, 2, . . .

• By the binomial formula,

zero on (0, ∞) by the assumption

z }| {

(α + β)N+1− (α + γ)N+1

= αN+1− αN+1

| {z }

zero on R

(j =0)

+ (N +1) αN ∗ β − αN ∗ γ

(j =1) +

N

X

j =2

N +1 j



αN+1−j∗ βj − αN+1−j ∗ γj

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞) by the induction hypothesis



+ βN+1− γN+1

| {z }

zero on (0, ∞)

. (j = N +2)

(50)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Thus, 0 = (N + 1) αN ∗ β − αN∗ γ

on (0, ∞).

• This is the desired result for n = N, k = 1.

• Larger values of k: induction within induction.

(51)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Thus, 0 = (N + 1) αN ∗ β − αN∗ γ

on (0, ∞).

• This is the desired result for n = N, k = 1.

• Larger values of k: induction within induction.

(52)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Thus, 0 = (N + 1) αN ∗ β − αN∗ γ

on (0, ∞).

• This is the desired result for n = N, k = 1.

• Larger values of k: induction within induction.

(53)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(54)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(55)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then, σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(56)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(57)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(58)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(59)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(60)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(61)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(62)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• Suppose that

1(0,∞)N ∗ βk) = 1(0,∞)N ∗ γk) for k = 1, 2, . . . , K − 1.

• Then,

σ ∗ β = (1(−∞,0]σ) ∗ β + (1(0,∞)σ) ∗ β

1(0,∞)N ∗ βK)

=

1(0,∞) ( αN ∗ βK −1

| {z }

σ

) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ βK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ γK −1) ∗ β

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ γK −1) ∗ β

=

1(0,∞)N∗ β) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N ∗ β) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

= 1(0,∞) 1(0,∞)N∗ γ) ∗ γK −1

=

1(0,∞)N ∗ γK).

(63)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . . w

w

 β = γ.

• Equivalently: it is not possible to have

1(0,∞)n∗ (β − γ)) =0 for all n = 0, 1, . . . and α 6= 0, β − γ 6= 0.

• We proceed by contradiction.

(64)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . . w

w

 β = γ.

• Equivalently: it is not possible to have

1(0,∞)n∗ (β − γ)) =0 for all n = 0, 1, . . . and α 6= 0, β − γ 6= 0.

• We proceed by contradiction.

(65)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We prove that

1(0,∞)n∗ β) = 1(0,∞)n∗ γ)for all n = 0, 1, . . . w

w

 β = γ.

• Equivalently: it is not possible to have

1(0,∞)n∗ (β − γ)) =0 for all n = 0, 1, . . . and α 6= 0, β − γ 6= 0.

• We proceed by contradiction.

(66)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We know that αn∗ (β − γ)is concentrated on (−∞, 0]

for all n = 1, 2, . . .

• Dene analytic extensions of characteristic functions: f (z) =

Z

(0,∞)

eiztα(dt) (Im z > 0) g (z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eizt(β − γ)(dt) (Im z 6 0) hn(z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eiztn∗ (β − γ))(dt) (Im z 6 0).

• We know that

(f (z))ng (z) = hn(z) for z ∈ R.

(67)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We know that αn∗ (β − γ)is concentrated on (−∞, 0]

for all n = 1, 2, . . .

• Dene analytic extensions of characteristic functions:

f (z) = Z

(0,∞)

eiztα(dt) (Im z > 0) g (z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eizt(β − γ)(dt) (Im z 6 0) hn(z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eiztn∗ (β − γ))(dt) (Im z 6 0).

• We know that

(f (z))ng (z) = hn(z) for z ∈ R.

(68)

Introduction Detailed statement Idea of the proof Algebra Complex analysis

• We know that αn∗ (β − γ)is concentrated on (−∞, 0]

for all n = 1, 2, . . .

• Dene analytic extensions of characteristic functions:

f (z) = Z

(0,∞)

eiztα(dt) (Im z > 0) g (z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eizt(β − γ)(dt) (Im z 6 0) hn(z) =

Z

(−∞,0]

eiztn∗ (β − γ))(dt) (Im z 6 0).

• We know that

(f (z))ng (z) = hn(z) for z ∈ R.

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

In this work, the problem of determin- ing an upper bound for the cp-rank of completely posi- tive matrices is reduced to the problem of determining the maximal number of

We let Y → ∞, and the main term (which is in our case a power of Y , while in the case of the Selberg trace formula the main term is log Y ) will cancel out.. An interesting feature

There are two differences with respect to [1]: In [1], the Proposition does not appear in this generality, and here a different choice of Banach function spaces eliminates any

S is conceived as a topological space with the topology determined by the

In this note we prove two theorems connecting the algebraic structure of Lie algebras of foliated vector fields with the smooth structure of a Riemannian foliation.. It is known

For “(i)→(ii)” we first observe that, if C is a countable structured algebra and B ⊆ P(Z) is the algebra which is generated by the arithmetic sequences and the finite sets, then

The detailed objectives within the presented works are: analysis of road safety in Poland; analysis of road accidents related to children, and the analysis of initiatives and

First of all the calculus of Melin is restricted to stratified nilpotent groups, whereas the extension offered here is valid for general homogeneous groups.. Another improve-