• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Suppose that (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) are topo- logical probability spaces, that is, probability spaces with topologies such that every open set is measurable

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Suppose that (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) are topo- logical probability spaces, that is, probability spaces with topologies such that every open set is measurable"

Copied!
11
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

147 (1995)

Products of completion regular measures

by

D. H. F r e m l i n (Colchester) and S. G r e k a s (Athens)

Abstract. We investigate the products of topological measure spaces, discussing con- ditions under which all open sets will be measurable for the simple completed product measure, and under which the product of completion regular measures will be completion regular. In passing, we describe a new class of spaces on which all completion regular Borel probability measures are τ -additive, and which have other interesting properties.

1. Introduction. Suppose that (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) are topo- logical probability spaces, that is, probability spaces with topologies such that every open set is measurable. We can form product measures on X × Y in various ways. First, we have the ordinary completed product measure λ derived by Carath´eodory’s method from the outer measure λ, where

λC = infn X

i∈N

µEiνFi: Ei∈ Σ, Fi∈ T ∀i ∈ N, C ⊆ [

i∈N

Ei× Fi o

. It can happen that λ is again a topological measure in that every open set in X × Y , for the product topology, is λ-measurable, but even for apparently well-behaved spaces (e.g., completion regular compact Radon probability spaces) this is not necessarily true (see [4]); the conditions under which it occurs are not well understood.

For a wide variety of important cases, it is known that λ does at least have an extension to a topological measure. Recall that a topological probability space (X, T, Σ, µ) is τ -additive if µ(S

G) = supG∈GµG for every non-empty upwards-directed family G of open sets. If (X, T, Σ, µ) is a topological prob- ability space, and (Y, S, T, ν) is a τ -additive topological probability space, then we have a topological measure λR on X × Y , given by setting

λRC =R

νCxµ(dx)

for Borel sets C ⊆ X × Y , writing Cx = {y : (x, y) ∈ C} for C ⊆ X × Y , x ∈ X; for consistency with other constructions, we will take it that λR is

1991 Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary 28C15.

[27]

(2)

to be the completion of its restriction to the Borel sets of X × Y . If now µ is also τ -additive then we have a similar measure λ0R given by

λ0RC =R

µCyν(dy)

for Borel C ⊆ X × Y , writing Cy = {x : (x, y) ∈ C}, and under these circumstances λR and λ0R are both τ -additive, therefore equal (since they agree on open rectangles). (See [18]. We remark that if µ and ν are both Radon measures, then so is λR= λ0R.) On Borel sets in the domain of λ, λ agrees with λR and λ0R if these are defined (using Fubini’s theorem on λ);

so if µ and ν are inner regular for the Borel sets—for instance, if they are completions of Borel measures—then λR, if it is defined, will extend λ, and λ will be a topological measure iff it is equal to λR.

Yet another aspect of the problem concerns the algebra Σ bσT , the σ-algebra of subsets of X × Y generated by {E × F : E ∈ Σ, F ∈ T }. λ is the completion of its restriction to Σ bσT —that is, it is inner regular for Σ bσT —so (if ν is τ -additive and µ, ν are inner regular for the Borel sets) λ = λR iff λR is inner regular for Σ bσT .

While the original impulse to study such questions arose from a simple desire to understand the nature of product Radon measures, there are im- portant problems in functional analysis which depend on the analysis here;

see, for instance, the distinction between “stable” and “R-stable” set which is necessary in [20], §9.

An allied question refers to “completion regular” spaces. Let us say that a topological measure space (X, T, Σ, µ) is completion regular if µ is inner regular for the zero sets (that is, sets of the form f−1[{0}] for some continu- ous f : X → R). Note that if B0= B0(X) is the Baire σ-algebra of X, that is, the σ-algebra generated by the zero sets in X, then µ¹B0is necessarily in- ner regular for the zero sets ([6], Theorem 4.2), so (X, T, Σ, µ) is completion regular iff µ is inner regular for B0. Many important spaces are completion regular; in particular, if X is a locally compact topological group and µ is (left or right) Haar measure on X, then µ is completion regular ([13], or [10],

§64, Theorem I), and if X is a product of compact metric spaces, and µ is a product of strictly positive Radon probabilities on the factors, then µ is completion regular ([12], Theorem 3, or [1], Theorem 3). Now the question is, when is the product of completion regular measures again completion regular? Because B0(X × Y ) always includes B0(X) bσB0(Y ) (and these are equal if X and Y are compact), the “product” in this question should be taken to be a topological product measure; normally, of course, the prod- uct measure λR discussed above. If (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) are com- pact completion regular topological probability spaces, with ν τ -additive, then we see that λR is completion regular precisely when all open sets are λ-measurable.

(3)

A variety of conditions have been found which are sufficient to ensure that open sets are λ-measurable, or that λR is completion regular. Most of those with which we are acquainted amount to special cases of the main result of the present paper, which is based on a particular topological con- dition on one of the factors. Recall that a Hausdorff space is dyadic if it is a continuous image of {0, 1}I for some set I. For the elementary properties of dyadic spaces see [3], 3.12.12 and 4.5.9–11; the essential ones relevant to us here are that

(i) compact metric spaces are dyadic, (ii) finite unions of dyadic spaces are dyadic, (iii) zero sets in dyadic spaces are dyadic, (iv) all products of dyadic spaces are dyadic,

(v) compact Hausdorff topological groups are dyadic

([16]; see also [21] and [2], pp. 93–94). We generalise this concept by say- ing that a topological space is quasi-dyadic if it is the continuous image of a product of separable metrizable spaces. Now our first result is that if (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) are τ -additive topological probability spaces, and one of them is quasi-dyadic and completion regular, then every open set in X × Y is λ-measurable (Theorem 5). It follows that if both factors are completion regular, so is λR. The argument of Theorem 5 depends on both factors having τ -additive measures. As it happens, however, this as- sumption can be omitted in the case of the quasi-dyadic factor, because any completion regular topological probability on a quasi-dyadic space is τ -additive (Theorem 4).

Of course, these results have consequences for the product of many fac- tors. If we have finitely many completion regular quasi-dyadic topological probability spaces (Xα, Tα, Σα, µα), then every open set in Z = Q

αXα is measurable for the simple product measure on Z; if we have infinitely many such spaces, and all but countably many of the µαare strictly positive (that is, give non-zero measure to every non-empty open set), the same will be true on the infinite product (Corollary 6).

We should mention the following known special cases of these results.

(i) Kakutani’s theorem on the products of measures on compact metric spaces, already discussed, is of course the fundamental version of Corollary 6.

(ii) [1], Theorem 3, allows one factor to be non-metrizable, and intro- duces the asymmetry to be found in the hypotheses of our Theorem 5.

(iii) [9], Theorem 3.1, covers the case in which the quasi-dyadic factor is actually a product of separable metric spaces; it strengthens Theorem 2 of [7] and the main theorem of [8].

(iv) Concerning our Theorem 4, the case in which X is itself a product of separable metric spaces is given in [9], Theorem 3.1.

(4)

For simplicity, we express our results in terms of probability measures. Of course, everything we say about finite products applies at least to all totally finite measures, and much of it can be extended to non-σ-finite measures if care is taken over the definitions of the product measures.

2. Lemma. If hSαiα∈I is a family of separable metric spaces, then every member E of the Baire σ-algebra of S =Q

α∈ISα depends on a countable subset J of I, that is, E = πJ−1[F ] for some F ⊆ Q

α∈JSα, writing πJ : Q

α∈ISαQ

α∈JSα for the canonical map.

P r o o f. See [19], or [3], 2.7.12.

3. To help give meaning to the concept of “quasi-dyadic” space, we give some elementary properties of these spaces.

Proposition. (a) A continuous image of a quasi-dyadic space is quasi- dyadic. Any product of quasi-dyadic spaces is quasi-dyadic.

(b) A space with countable network is quasi-dyadic.

(c) If X is a quasi-dyadic space and Y belongs to the Baire σ-algebra of X, then Y is quasi-dyadic.

(d) A countable union of quasi-dyadic subspaces of a given topological space is quasi-dyadic.

P r o o f. (a) Immediate from the definition.

(b) (See [3], 3.1.J and elsewhere, for basic facts concerning countable networks.) Let D be a countable network for the topology of X. On X let

∼ be the equivalence relation in which x ∼ y if they belong to just the same members of D; let Y be the space X/∼ of equivalence classes, and θ : X → Y the canonical map. Y has a separable metrizable topology with base {θ[D] : D ∈ D} ∪ {θ[X \ D] : D ∈ D}. Let I be any set such that

#({0, 1}I) ≥ #(X), and for each y ∈ Y let fy: {0, 1}I → y be a surjection.

Then we have a continuous surjection f : Y × {0, 1}I → X given by saying that f (y, z) = fy(z) for y ∈ Y , z ∈ {0, 1}I.

(c) Let hSαiα∈I be a family of separable metric spaces with product S and f : S → X a continuous surjection. Let A be the family of subsets of S which factor through countable sub-products, and E the set {E : E ⊆ X, f−1[E] ∈ A}. Then A and E are σ-algebras. By Lemma 2, every zero set in S belongs to A; consequently, every zero set in X belongs to E and E includes the Baire σ-algebra of X. But if E ∈ E, there is a countable J ⊆ I such that E = f [F ×Q

α∈I\JSα] for some F ⊆ Q

α∈JSα; and F , being a subset of a countable product of separable metric spaces, is separable and metrizable, so E is quasi-dyadic.

(d) If En ⊆ X is quasi-dyadic for each n ∈ N, then Z = N ×Q

n∈NEn is quasi-dyadic, and f : Z → S

n∈NEn is a continuous surjection, where f (n, hxiii∈N) = xn.

(5)

R e m a r k. We include (b) to emphasize that the ideas here may be ap- plied to non-Hausdorff spaces. Any continuous image of a product of spaces with countable networks will be quasi-dyadic.

4. Theorem. Let (X, T, Σ, µ) be a quasi-dyadic completion regular topo- logical probability space. Then µ is τ -additive.

P r o o f. Suppose, if possible, otherwise.

(a) The first step is the standard reduction to the case in which X is covered by open sets of zero measure. In detail: suppose that X0 is a quasi-dyadic space and µ0 is a completion regular topological probability measure on X0which is not τ -additive. Let G be an upwards-directed family of open sets in X0 such that µ0(S

G) > supG∈Gµ0G. Set µ1E = µ0E − supG∈Gµ0(E ∩ G) for every Borel set E ⊆ X0; then µ1 is a completion regular Borel measure on X0, µ1G = 0 for every G ∈ G, and µ1(S

G) > 0.

Let X ⊆ S

G be a Baire set such that µ1X > 0. Then X is quasi-dyadic (3c). For Borel sets E ⊆ X, set µE = µ1E/µ1X; then µ is a completion regular Borel probability measure on X, and {X ∩ G : G ∈ G} is a cover of X by open negligible sets.

(b) Now let hSαiα∈I be a family of separable metric spaces such that there is a continuous surjection f : S → X, where S =Q

α∈ISα. For each α ∈ I let Bα be a countable base for the topology of Sα. For J ⊆ I let C(J) be the family of all subsets of S expressible in the form

{s : s(α) ∈ Bα ∀α ∈ K},

where K is a finite subset of J and Bα ∈ Bα for each α ∈ K; thus C(I) is a base for the topology of S. Set C0(J) = {U : U ∈ C(J), µf [U ] = 0} for each J ⊆ I.

For each negligible set E ⊆ X, let hFn(E)in∈Nbe a family of zero subsets of X \ E such that supn∈NµFn= 1. Then each f−1[Fn(E)] is a zero subset of S, so there is a countable set M (E) ⊆ I such that all the sets f−1[Fn(E)]

depend on M (E) (Lemma 2). Let J be the family of countable subsets J of I such that M (f [U ]) ⊆ J for every U ∈ C0(J); then J is cofinal with [I]≤ω, that is, every countable subset of I is included in some member of J . (If we start from any countable subset J0 of I and set

Jn+1= J0[

{M (f [U ]) : U ∈ C0(Jn)}

for each n ∈ N, then S

n∈NJn ∈ J .) (c) For each J ∈ J , set

QJ =\ n [

n∈N

Fn(f [U ]) : U ∈ C0(J) o

.

Then µQJ = 1 and f−1[QJ] depends on J.

(6)

If G ⊆ X is a negligible open set, then G ∩ QJ = ∅ whenever J ∈ J and there is a negligible Baire set Q ⊇ G such that f−1[Q] depends on J.

For set H = πJ−1J[f−1[G]]], where πJ : S → Q

α∈JSα is the canonical map; then H is a union of members of C(J), because f−1[G] is open. Also, because f−1[Q] depends on J, H ⊆ f−1[Q], so f [H] ⊆ Q and µf [H] = 0;

thus all the members of C(J) included in H actually belong to C0(J), and H ∩f−1[QJ] = ∅. But this means that f−1[G]∩f−1[QJ] = ∅ and G∩QJ = ∅, as claimed.

In particular, if G is a negligible open set in X, then G∩QJ = ∅ whenever J ∈ J and J ⊇ M (G).

(d) If J ∈ J , there are s, s0 ∈ f−1[QJ] such that s¹J = s0¹J and f (s), f (s0) can be separated by open sets in X. To see this, start from any x ∈ QJ and take a negligible open set G including x (recall that our hypothesis is that X is covered by negligible open sets). For each n ∈ N let hn : X → R be a continuous function such that Fn(G) = h−1n [{0}]. We know that G∩QJ6= ∅, while G ⊆ X \ (S

n∈NFn(G) ∩ QJ), which is a negligible Baire set; by (c), f−1[X \ (S

n∈NFn(G) ∩ QJ)] does not depend on J, and there must be some n such that f−1[Fn(G)∩QJ] does not depend on J. Accordingly, there must be s, s0∈ S such that s¹J = s0¹J, s ∈ f−1[Fn(G) ∩ QJ] and s06∈ f−1[Fn(G)

∩ QJ]. Now s and s0 both belong to f−1[QJ], because f−1[QJ] depends on J; while f (s) ∈ Fn(G) and f (s0) 6∈ Fn(G), so hn(f (s)) 6= hn(f (s0)) and f (s), f (s0) can be separated by open sets.

(e) We are now ready to embark on the central construction of the argu- ment. We may choose inductively, for ordinals ξ < ω1, sets Jξ ∈ J , negligible open sets Gξ, G0ξ⊆ X, points sξ, s0ξ ∈ S, sets Uξ, Vξ, Vξ0 ∈ C(I) such that

• Jη ⊆ Jξ, Uη, Vη, Vη0 all belong to C(Jξ), Gη∩ QJξ = ∅ whenever η <

ξ < ω1 (using the results of (b) and (c) to choose Jξ);

• sξ¹Jξ = s0ξ¹Jξ, sξ ∈ f−1[QJξ], f (sξ) and f (s0ξ) can be separated by open sets in X (using (d) to choose sξ, s0ξ);

• Gξ, G0ξ are disjoint negligible open sets containing f (sξ), f (s0ξ) respec- tively (choosing Gξ, G0ξ);

• Uξ ∈ C(Jξ), Vξ, Vξ0∈ C(I \ Jξ), sξ ∈ Uξ∩ Vξ ⊆ f−1[Gξ], s0ξ∈ Uξ∩ Vξ0 f−1[G0ξ] (choosing Uξ, Vξ, Vξ0, using the fact that sξ¹Jξ = s0ξ¹Jξ).

On completing this construction, take for each ξ < ω1 a finite set Kξ Jξ+1 such that Uξ, Vξ and Vξ0 all belong to C(Kξ). By the ∆-system lemma ([14], II.1.5), there is an uncountable A ⊆ ω1 such that hKξiξ∈A is a ∆- system with root K say, that is, Kξ ∩ Kη = K for all distinct ξ, η ∈ A.

For ξ ∈ A, express Uξ as eUξ∩ Uξ0 where eUξ ∈ C(K), Uξ0 ∈ C(Kξ\ K). Then there are only countably many possibilities for eUξ, so there is an uncountable B ⊆ A such that eUξ is constant for ξ ∈ B; write eU for the constant value.

(7)

Let C ⊆ B be an uncountable set, not containing min A, such that Kξ\ K does not meet Jη whenever ξ, η ∈ C and η < ξ. Let D ⊆ C be such that D and C \ D are both uncountable.

Note that K ⊆ Kη ⊆ Jξ whenever η, ξ ∈ A and η < ξ, so that K ⊆ Jξ

for every ξ ∈ C. Consequently, Uξ0, Vξ and Vξ0 all belong to C(Kξ \ K) for every ξ ∈ C.

(f) Consider the open set

G = [

ξ∈D

Gξ ⊆ X.

At this point the argument divides.

C a s e 1. Suppose µ(G ∩ f [ eU ]) > 0. Then there is a Baire set Q ⊆ G such that µ(Q ∩ f [ eU ]) > 0. Let J ⊆ I be a countable set such that f−1[Q]

depends on J. Let γ ∈ C \ D be so large that Kξ \ K does not meet J for any ξ ∈ A with ξ ≥ γ. Then Q ∩ QJγ ∩ f [ eU ] is not empty; take s ∈ eU ∩ f−1[Q ∩ QJγ]. Because the Kξ \ K are disjoint from each other and from J ∪ Jγ for ξ ∈ D, ξ > γ, we may modify s to form s0 such that s0¹J ∪ Jγ = s¹J ∪ Jγ and s0 ∈ Uξ0∩ Vξ0 for every ξ ∈ D, ξ > γ; now s0 ∈ eU (because K ⊆ Jγ), so s0∈ eU ∩ Uξ0∩ Vξ0⊆ f−1[G0ξ] and f (s0) 6∈ Gξ whenever ξ ∈ D, ξ > γ. On the other hand, if ξ ∈ D and ξ < γ, Gξ∩ QJγ = ∅, while s0∈ f−1[QJγ] (because f−1[QJγ] depends on Jγ), so again f (s0) 6∈ Gξ.

Thus f (s0) 6∈ G. But s0¹J = s¹J so f (s) ∈ Q ⊆ G, which is impossible.

This contradiction disposes of the possibility that µ(G ∩ f [ eU ]) > 0.

C a s e 2. Suppose that µ(G∩f [ eU ]) = 0. In this case there is a negligible Baire set Q ⊇ G ∩ f [ eU ]. Let J ⊆ I be a countable set such that f−1[Q]

depends on J. Let ξ ∈ D be such that Kξ\ K does not meet J. Then U ∩ Ue ξ0∩ Vξ⊆ f−1[Gξ] ∩ eU ⊆ f−1[G ∩ f [ eU ]] ⊆ f−1[Q],

so eU ⊆ f−1[Q], because Uξ0 ∩ Vξ is a non-empty member of C(I \ J). But this means that µf [ eU ] = 0 and µf [Uξ] = 0. On the other hand, we have sξ∈ Uξ∩ f−1[QJξ], so Uξ 6∈ C0(Jξ) and µf [Uξ] > 0.

Thus this route is also blocked and we must abandon the original hypoth- esis that there is a quasi-dyadic space with a completion regular topological probability measure which is not τ -additive.

5. Theorem. Let (X, T, Σ, µ) and (Y, S, T, ν) be topological probability spaces; suppose that (X, T, Σ, µ) is completion regular and quasi-dyadic, and that (Y, S, T, ν) is τ -additive. Then every open set in X × Y is measurable for the ordinary completed product measure λ on X × Y .

(8)

P r o o f. Suppose, if possible, otherwise. By Theorem 4, we know that µ is τ -additive. We may suppose that the domain T of ν is precisely the algebra of Borel subsets of Y , since restricting the domain of ν will tend to decrease the domain of λ.

(a) There must be a closed set C ⊆ X × Y which is not λ-measurable.

Because λR is τ -additive, λR((X × Y ) \ C) ≤ λ((X × Y ) \ C); but also λRC ≤ λC, so in fact we must have λRC = λC.

We are supposing that X is quasi-dyadic; take a family hSαiα∈I of separable metric spaces and a continuous surjection f : S → X, where S =Q

α∈ISα. Choose Bα and define C(J), for J ⊆ I, as in part (b) of the proof of Theorem 4.

(b) If J ⊆ I is countable, there are G, U , V such that G ⊆ Y is open, U ∈ C(J), V ∈ C(I \J), V 6= ∅, C ∩(f [U ∩V ]×G) = ∅ and λ(C ∩(f [U ]×G)) > 0.

To see this, write

GU = {G : G ⊆ Y is open,

∃V ∈ C(I \ J), V 6= ∅, C ∩ (f [U ∩ V ] × G)) = ∅}, GU = [

GU,

and choose FU ⊇ f [U ] such that FU ∈ Σ and µFU = µ(f [U ]), for each U ∈ C(J). We have GU ∈ T for every U , and C(J) is countable, so

C1= (X × Y ) \ [

U ∈C(J)

FU × GU ∈ Σ bσT ;

also C1⊆ C because C is closed and

{f [U ∩ V ] × G : G ⊆ Y is open, U ∈ C(J), V ∈ C(I \ J)}

is a network for the topology of X × Y . So λR(C \ C1) = λRC − λRC1 = λ(C \ C1) > 0, because C is not λ-measurable. Accordingly, there is a U ∈ C(J) such that λR(C ∩ (FU× GU)) > 0. Next, because ν is τ -additive, there is a countable G ⊆ GU such that ν(GU \S

G) = 0, and now λR(C ∩ (FU ×S

G)) = λR(C ∩ (FU × GU)) > 0, so there is a G ∈ G such that λR(C ∩ (FU× G)) > 0, that is,

R

FU

ν(Cx∩ G) µ(dx) > 0.

But this means that µ{x : x ∈ FU, ν(Cx∩ G) > 0} > 0, so that µ{x : x ∈ f [U ], ν(Cx∩ G) > 0} > 0, and λ(C ∩ (f [U ] × G)) > 0. Finally, because G ∈ GU, there is a V ∈ C(I \ J) such that C ∩ (f [U ∩ V ] × G) = ∅.

(c) We may therefore choose inductively families hJξiξ<ω1, hGξiξ<ω1, hUξiξ<ω1, hVξiξ<ω1 in such a way that, for every ξ < ω1,

(9)

• Jξ is a countable subset of I,

• Gξ is an open subset of Y ,

• Uξ ∈ C(Jξ), Vξ∈ C(I \ Jξ), Vξ6= ∅,

• C ∩ (f [Uξ∩ Vξ] × Gξ) = ∅,

• λ(C ∩ (f [Uξ] × Gξ)) > 0,

S

η<ξJη ⊆ Jξ,

• Vξ∈ C(Jξ+1).

For each ξ < ω1, let Kξ be a finite subset of I such that Uξ, Vξ both belong to C(Kξ). By the ∆-system lemma, there is an uncountable set A ⊆ ω1such that hKξiξ∈A is a ∆-system with root K say. Express each Uξ as eUξ ∩ Uξ0 where eUξ ∈ C(K) and Uξ0 ∈ C(Kξ\ K); because C(K) is countable, there is a eU such that B = {ξ : ξ ∈ A, ξ 6= min A, eUξ = eU } is uncountable. Note that µ(f [ eU ]) ≥ µ(f [Uξ]) > 0 for any ξ ∈ B. Also, K ⊆ Kmin A ⊆ Jξ for each ξ ∈ B, so Vξ∈ C(Kξ\ Jξ) ⊆ C(Kξ\ K) for each ξ ∈ B.

(e) Set Hζ = S

ξ∈B, ξ≥ζGξ for each ζ < ω1. The family hνHζiζ<ω1 is non-increasing in R, so there must be a δ < ω1 such that νHζ = νHδ whenever δ ≤ ζ < ω1. Now consider

D = C ∩ (X × Hδ).

Because D ⊇ C ∩ (f [Uξ] × Gξ) for any ξ ∈ B \ δ, λRD > 0. Set F = {x : ν(Cx∩ Hδ) > 0} ⊆ X;

because Fubini’s theorem applies to λR, µF > 0. At this point we use the hypothesis that µ is completion regular to see that there is a zero set F0⊆ F with µF0 > µF − µ(f [ eU ]). Now W = eU ∩ f−1[F0] is non-empty because F0∩ f [ eU ] is non-empty. Let J ⊆ I be a countable set such that K ⊆ J and W depends on J (see §§2–3 above). Let ζ < ω1 be such that ζ ≥ δ and Kξ\ K = ∅ for every ξ ∈ B \ ζ; this exists because hKξ\ Kiξ∈B is disjoint.

Take any w ∈ W , and modify it to obtain w0∈ S such that w0¹J = w¹J and w0 ∈ Uξ0∩ Vξ for every ξ ∈ B \ ζ;

this is possible because Uξ0∩Vξ ∈ C(Kξ\K) for each ξ ∈ B\ζ, and hKξ\Kiξ∈B is disjoint. Set x = f (w0); then x ∈ F0⊆ F , so νDx > 0.

If ξ ∈ B \ ζ, then x ∈ f [ eU ∩ Uξ0 ∩ Vξ] = f [Uξ ∩ Vξ], so (x, y) 6∈ C for y ∈ Gξ and Cx∩ Gξ = ∅. Thus

Dx ⊆ Hδ\ Hζ, and µHζ < µHδ, contrary to the choice of δ.

This contradiction proves the theorem.

6. Corollary. Let h(Xα, Tα, Σα, µα)iα∈I be a family of quasi-dyadic completion regular topological probability spaces, and suppose that all but

(10)

countably many of the µαare strictly positive. Then the simple (completed) product measure on Z = Q

α∈IXα is also a completion regular topological measure.

P r o o f. For finite I, this is a simple induction on #(I), using Theo- rems 4 and 5. For infinite I, use Theorem 2.9 of [9], which says that if all the τ -additive topological product measures on finite subproducts are com- pletion regular, and all but countably many of the factor measures µα are strictly positive, the τ -additive topological product measure on Z will also be completion regular, and therefore will coincide with the simple completed product measure.

7. R e m a r k s. In Theorems 4 and 5 it is not of course necessary that X itself should be quasi-dyadic. If (X, T, Σ, µ) is a completion regular τ - additive topological probability space in which µ is inner regular for the quasi-dyadic subsets of X, this will do just as well. This will be so, for instance, if X is an open subset of a dyadic space and µ is a completion regular Radon measure on X.

In the same way, it will be enough, in Corollary 6, if every µα is inner regular for the quasi-dyadic subsets of Xα.

Theorem 4 can be generalized as follows: Let X be a quasi-dyadic space and I a proper σ-ideal of subsets of X such that for every open G ⊆ X there are Baire subsets E, F of X such that E ⊆ G ⊆ F and F \ E ∈ I. Then X cannot be covered by the open sets belonging to I; indeed,S

{G : G ∈ I, G is open} ∈ I.

We do not know of a ZFC example of a completion regular measure on a completely regular Hausdorff space which is not τ -additive. (We note that there is a probability measure on the Baire σ-algebra of Rc which is not τ -additive, in the strong sense that Rc is covered by the negligible cozero sets; see [17], or [6], 15.4; but this measure is not completion regular.)

References

[1] J. C h o k s i and D. H. F r e m l i n, Completion regular measures on product spaces, Math. Ann. 241 (1979), 113–128.

[2] W. W. C o m f o r t, K.-H. H o f f m a n n and D. R e m u s, Topological groups and semi- groups, pp. 57–114 in [11].

[3] R. E n g e l k i n g, General Topology, Sigma Ser. Pure Math. 6, Heldermann, 1989.

[4] D. H. F r e m l i n, Products of Radon measures: a counterexample, Canad. Math.

Bull. 19 (1976), 285–289.

[5] Z. F r o l´ık (ed.), General Topology and its Relations to Modern Analysis and Algebra VI , Proc. Sixth Prague Topological Sympos., 1986, Heldermann, 1988.

[6] R. J. G a r d n e r and W. F. P f e f f e r, Borel measures, pp. 961–1043 in [15].

(11)

[7] S. G r e k a s and C. G r y l l a k i s, Completion regular measures on product spaces with application to the existence of Baire strong liftings, Illinois J. Math. 35 (1991), 260–268.

[8] C. G r y l l a k i s, Products of completion regular measures, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc.

103 (1988), 563–568.

[9] C. G r y l l a k i s and G. K o u m o u l l i s, Completion regularity and τ -additivity of mea- sures on product spaces, Compositio Math. 73 (1990), 329–344.

[10] P. H a l m o s, Measure Theory, van Nostrand, 1950.

[11] M. H uˇse k and J. v a n M i l l (eds.), Recent Progress in General Topology, Elsevier, 1992.

[12] S. K a k u t a n i, Notes on infinite product spaces II , Proc. Imperial Acad. Tokyo 19 (1943), 184–188.

[13] S. K a k u t a n i and K. K o d a i r a, ¨Uber das Haarsche Mass in der lokal bikompakten Gruppe, ibid. 20 (1944), 444–450.

[14] K. K u n e n, Set Theory, North-Holland, 1980.

[15] K. K u n e n and J. E. V a u g h a n (eds.), Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology, North- Holland, 1984.

[16] V. K u z’ m i n o v, On a hypothesis of P. S. Aleksandrov in the theory of topological groups, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 125 (1959), 727–729 (in Russian).

[17] W. M o r a n, The additivity of measures on completely regular spaces, J. London Math. Soc. 43 (1968), 633–639.

[18] P. R e s s e l, Some continuity and measurability results on spaces of measures, Math.

Scand. 40 (1977), 69–78.

[19] K. A. R o s s and A. H. S t o n e, Products of separable spaces, Amer. Math. Monthly 71 (1964), 398–403.

[20] M. T a l a g r a n d, Pettis integral and measure theory, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 307 (1984).

[21] V. V. U s p e n s k i˘ı, Why compact groups are dyadic, pp. 601–610 in [5].

MATHEMATICS DEPARTMENT SECTION OF MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS

UNIVERSITY OF ESSEX PANEPISTEMIOPOLIS

COLCHESTER CO4 3SQ 15784 ATHENS, GREECE

ENGLAND

E-mail: FREMDH@ESSEX.AC.UK

Received 15 February 1994

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

Luukkainen for his observations which allowed me to discover the above mistakes.. INSTITUTE OF

Let p, q be different

(b) Find the probability that a randomly selected student from this class is studying both Biology and

Having this property we were able to renorm L 1 , in such a way that the solution set of (*) is the set of fixed points of certain multivalued contraction and then apply the BCF

For which locally compact σ-compact Hausdorff topological groups does the characterization obtained in Theorem 1 hold.. S.concentrated and spread

We now make a start towards the proof of the Main Theorem with some preliminary technical results..

Let us now recall the notion of α-proper forcing for a countable ordinal α saying that, given an ∈-chain of length α of countable elementary sum- bodels of some large enough structure

After the preliminary Section 2 we discuss the admissible convergence to the boundary in Section 3, where we also formulate the main theorem and make some comments.. The proof of