• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Time Topology for Some Classical and Quantum Non-Relativistic Systems

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Time Topology for Some Classical and Quantum Non-Relativistic Systems"

Copied!
18
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

Stanisław Olszewski

Time Topology for Some Classical

and Quantum Non-Relativistic

Systems

Studia Philosophiae Christianae 28/1, 119-135

(2)

S tu d ia P h ilosop h iae C hristianae A TK

28(1992)1

ST A N IS Ł A W OLSZEW SKI

TIME TOPOLOGY FOR SOME CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM NON-RELATIVISTIC SYSTEMS

1. Introduction. 2. The observer; h is birth, life and d eath. 3. T w o k in d s of the scale of tim e. 4. S im p le e x a m p les of an e x te r n a l observer. 5. P ertu rb ation of a q u an tu m -m ech a n ica l sy stem and top ology of tim e. S. P ertu rb ation en erg y obtained from a circular scale of tim e. 7. E li­ m in a tio n p rin cip le for eq u al tim es. 8. S u rvey.

1. IN T RO D U C TIO N

A ccording to E. K a n t tim e an d space a re tw o ’’fo rm s” of perception. The background of th eir m eaning is m ain ly in ­ tu itio n al \ In physics tim e is — in principle — a coordinate: in n o n -relativ istic physics, th is coordinate m ay v a ry in d ep en ­ d en tly of th e spatial coordinates, w h ereas in a relativ istic ca­ se the tim e coordinate is coupled w ith its sp atial co u n terp arts. This situ atio n holds eq u ally fo r classic a n d q u a n tu m theories. In a sta tio n a ry state of a system described by th e n o n -re la ­ tivistic q u a n tu m m echanics, tim e e n te rs only th e phase fac to r of the w ave fu n ction w hich has no influence on th e calculated av erag ed q u a n titie s corresponding to th e observed data. In effect, in a sta tio n a ry sta te no change in tim e of th e observed q u a n titie s m ay occur.

In tu itio n ally, in classical a n d q u a n tu m m echanics (as w ell as in special relativ istic theory) we assum e th e tim e coordina­ te m ay v a ry from a m inus in fin ity called ’’the p a st” to a p lus in fin ity called ’’th e f u tu r e ”. A tim e scale of this k in d w e call linear; see Fig. 1. The purpose of th is p ap er is to indicate th a t a tim e scale w hich is d iffe re n t th an lin e a r m ay be — a t least m some cases — of a b e tte r use. In our considerations w e disreg ard fu lly th e relativ istic theo ry : w e n eglect the coupling betw een tim e and o th er (spatial) coordinates into one space- -tim e m etrics as w ell as the pro b lem of tim e in te rv a ls and

1 W. S. F ow ler, T h e D e v e l o p m e n t of S cie n tif ic M ethod, P ergam on P ress, O xford 1962.

(3)

th e ir m easurem ents. The tim e coordinate is assum ed (sim ilarly to L e ib n iz 2) solely to be a p a ra m e te r w hich allow s us to disting u ish b etw een ’’e a rlie r” an d „ la te r”.

The p roblem of tim e topology has its rich bibliography \ In this p a p e r we try to ap p roach th is p roblem on the basis of an analysis of sim ple physical system s, both classical an d q u antu m . For th e classical case we lim it ourselves to periodic system s. A ccording to T h irrin g 4 an alm ost periodic tim e evo­ lu tio n is a general p ro p e rty of sm all system s, w hereas fo r larg e system s this evolution exhib its a chaotic behav iour con­ nected to a m ixing o f th e observables. F or the q u a n tu m case w e exam ine th e tim e evolution of a system su b m itted to the action of a sm all e x te rn a l field called p e rtu rb a tio n an d deno­ ted b y V; w e consider only a system having n o n -d egenerate q uan tu m -m ech an ical states, so th e system energies correspond­ ing to d iffe re n t states are d ifferen t. B eyond the p e rtu rb a tio n V, w e assum e th e system is a fu lly isolated object.

We fo rm u late th e problem of tim e topology for a q u a n tu m - -m echanical : system as follows: In a v e ry d ista n t past, th e system w as in a u n p e rtu rb e d sta tio n a ry sta te (P) in w hich :— in th e absence of V — it could rem ain in fin itely. A t some m om en t th e system w as p e rtu rb e d by V, an d in a v e ry d ista n t fu tu re -it w ill be found in a n o th e r sta tio n a ry sta te (F); w e

2 G: W. L eibniz, Confe ss io Philosophi. Ein, Dialog, K losterinarm ,

F ra n k fu rt a/M., 1967.

3 H, Reichenba.ch, T h e P h il o s o p h y o f S p a c e an d T im e , D over P u b li­ cation s, N e w Y ork 1958; J. J. C, Sm art (ed.), P r o b l e m s of S p i c e an d

T im e , M acM illan, L ondon 1964; T. G old (ed.), T h e N a t u r e o f T im e,

C orn ell U n iv ersity P ress, Ithaca 1967; H. R eich en b ach , T h e D irectio n

of'-'Time, U n iv ersity of C alifornia P ress, B erk eley 1971; A.. Griinfoaum, P hilo so p h ica l P r o b l e m s o f S p a c e an d T im e , 2nd ed., A. R ied el,. D o r­

d recht 1973; J. R.. Lucas, A T r e a ti s e on T i m e an d S pace, M ethuen, L on ­ don 1973; L. Sklar, Space, T i m e an d S p a c e -t im e , U n iv e r sity of C a li­ fornia' P ress, B erk eley 1974; I. H in ck fu ss, T h e E x iste n c e of S p a ce 'an\d

T im e , C larendon P r e s s /O x f o r d 1975; G. N erlich, T h e S h a p e of .Space,

U n iv e r sity P ress, C am bridge 1976; W. H. N ew to n -S m ith , T h e S t r u c t u ­

re of T im e , R ou tled ge an d K eg a n P au l, L ondon 1980; G. J. W hitrow , T h e N a tu r a l P h il o s o p h y of T im e , C larendon P ress, O xford 1980;

D. H. M ellor, R eal T im e , U n iv e r sity P ess, C am bridge 1981; R. S w in ­ burne, S pace a n d T im e, 2nd ed., M acM illan, L ondon 1981; E. Jaques, . T h e F o r m of Time,. R u ssa k -H ein em a n n , N ew Y ork 1982; M. F ried m an n ,

F o u n d a tio n s of S p a c e - T im e T heorie s, P rin ceton U n iv ersity Press, P r in ­

ceton 1983; R. L e P o id ev in , R e la t io n i s m an d T e m p o r a l T o p o lo g y : P h y ­

sics, or M eta p h ysics ? , „The P h ilo so p h ica l Q uarterly” 40 (1990), 419—432.

' 4 W. T h ir r in g ,’ L e h r b u c h d e r M a t h e m a t is c h e n P h y s ik . B a n d ' _4:

(4)

assum e P φ F. The question w e p u t h e re is w h a t is th e kind of tim e p a th w hich is follow ed by th e system on its w ay fro m P to F. B efore we approach th e problem of a tim e p a th fo r a q u an tu m -m ech an ical case w e exam ine — in Section 2— 4.

— the tim e topology for classical periodic system s. 2. THE OBSERVER; H IS B IR TH , LIFE A N D D EA TH

As a firs t step, let us point out th a t a tim e toplogy can be a subjective notion depending both on th e p ro p erties of the ex am ined system as w ell as th e p erception ab ility of the ex am in er (an observer). We define th e o bserver as a being who can do (and register) m easurem ents. F o r exam ple, we m ay im agine an o bserver w h o can reg iste r solely th e coordinate- X of th e position of a body in a C artesian coordinate system . A nother observer can reg ister, say, th e x an d y coordinates of th is system ; th e th ird observer can m easure all th re e kinds of coordinates: x, y an d z. B eyond these coordinates w e m ay h av e observers w ho can m easure — for exam ple — one, o r m ore, velocity com ponents of the body; o th er observers can reg iste r o th er body prop erties, for exam ple its m ass. Finally , w e m ay im agine an o bserver whose percep tio n an d m easuring a b ility is infin ite. We call Him an E x te rn a l O bserver.

A ny observer who is able to accept only a fin ite set of observations of a system is an o bserver connected — in some w ay — w ith th a t sytem . He d iffers fro m a n o th e r observer w hose p erception ability, i.e. th e (finite) set of m easurem nts, w hich can be done by him on the system and reg istered, is differen t. It is easy to note th a t th e perception a b ility of an observer depends on th e system properties, in p a rtic u la r th e system com plexity. F o r exam ple, fo r a system w hich is a sta rig h t line identical w ith the x axis, th e re is no problem of how to m easu re th e space coordinates o th er th a n x; sim i­ la rly in o rd er to m easu re a position in the system w hich is a p lan e th ere is no p roblem of how to m easure m ore th a n two kinds of in d ep en d en t coordinates, say x an d y. L e t us assum e th a t beyond observables d iffe re n t th an tim e an y observer can also m easure tim e. This m eans th a t he is able to distinguish betw een an e a rlie r and a la te r event; an ev en t for an o bser­ v e r m eans — as a ru le — a m easu rem en t. The tim e m easu­ re m e n ts enable him to establish th e sequence of events. T he s e t of all m easu rem en ts in in sta n ts t ; enclosed w ith in an in te rv a l of tim e done in sequence by an observ er w e call th e life in te rv a l of th is observer. The e arliest of th e observations

(5)

done by th e o bserver (corresponding to th e sm allest tj) w e call his b irth ; the la te st observation (corresponding to th e larg est t;) w e call his death. We assum e th e n u m b er of o bser­ vation s in th e set of m easu rem en ts rep re sen tin g th e life of an observer is finite, although no lim it can be im posed a p rio ri on it.

The in sta n ts of tim e t; m easu red by an o bserver durin g his life can be rep re sen te d on the tim e scale given in Fig. 1. These in sta n ts fill·th e in te rv al BD; see Fig. la.

3. TW O K IN D S OF THE SC ALE OF TIM E

L et a sim ple (linear) h arm onic oscillator oscillate along th e X axis. W ith th e oscillator an o bserver is connected w ho can m easu re th e values of the x coordinate; a n y m ea su rem e n t of X is accom panied b y a corresponding m easu rem en t of t. T he oscillator moves, say, firs t in th e direction of positive x, n e x t it goes to negativ e x. We assum e th e o bserver s ta rts his m ea­ su re m e n ts im m ed iately a fte r th e oscillator m oves across th e point x = 0. This m eans th e life of th e o bserver s ta rts a t c e rta in position

χΒ = ε δ;0 (1)

for w h ich t = t B. N ex t x increases u n til th e positive value close to th e am p litud e of th e oscillator is atta in e d ; th e n x begins to decrease, becom ing in some in sta n t, a negative num b er. A t the sam e tim e th e sequence of th e m easured in sta n ts tj is an increasing set of num bers. A fter th e sm allest x is a tta in e d the v alu e of x increases. The larg e st of the increasing b u t negativ e x is some

XD = - s ' ^ o. (2) The n e x t m easu red valu e of x is

Xd+ 1 = s £ 0 ( 3 )

so

XD+1 == X

b

(4)

because w e assum e th a t th e ry th m of the oscillator as w ell as th a t of th e m easu rem en ts of χ rem ain s unchan ged in th e course of th e oscillations. This situ atio n rep e a ts in fin ite ly in accordance w ith th e d efinition of th e oscillator as a p erfectly perio dic system . An im p o rta n t fe a tu re of a p e rfe c t periodic system is th a t we have no physical p a ra m e te r w hich allow s

(6)

us to distinguish b etw een one oscillaltion period a n d an o th er. If we assum e th a t th e re exists a one-to-one correspondence betw een th e m easurem en ts of x an d those of t, the full perio­ dicity of the sytem im plies th e sam e periodic p ro p e rty fo r th e tim e variable. In effect, th e tim e scale for the oscillator should be n o t lin ear b u t form s a closed line leading to th e eq u ality

Id-;] — tB (5)

sim ilar to (4). This p ro p e rty is rep re sen te d in Fig. lb. Topolo­ gically the scale is eq u ivalen t to a circle; see Fig. 2. The life

betw een the b irth (tB) and th e death (tD) of the observer con­ n e c te d w ith the oscillator will re p e a t in fin ite ly a n d n o th in g in the system allow s for him to d etect the repetitio ns. These rep e titio n s can be discovered only by a n o th e r observer whose ability to do m easu rem en ts is larg er th a t th a t of the o bserver connected w ith the oscillator. Me call such an observer an e x te r­ nal observer (not capitalized). In o rd er to discover th e re p e ti­ tions of th e life of the observ er connected w ith th e oscillator, th e e x te rn al observer should have th e possib ility of counting th e oscillations. A n exam ple of such an e x te rn al o bserver is given in th e n e x t section.

4. SIM PLE E X A M PLE S OF A N E X T E R N A L OBSERVER L et us consider e a rth Z w hich circles abou t sun S along an ellipse. A n observer is connected w ith th e system . W e call him an in te rn a l o bserver (i.o.) an d assum e th e observer can m easu re only the distance r betw een S an d Z a n d can re g iste r th e in sta n ts of tim e t corresponding to d iffe re n t r. L et us assum e th e m easurin g ab ility (perception) of th e observer begins to w ork a t the sm allest possible r — r min. The firs t m easu rem en t r B gives th e sm allest valu e of the increasing r, w hereas th e last m easu rem en t, r D, gives th e sm allest valu e of th e decreasing r. The set of m easu rem en ts rep e a ts in fin ite ly w ith o u t th e possibility of detection of th is fac t by th e obser­ ver. Because of th is periodicity, th e p ercep tio n of th e obser­ v e r goes to zero and begins to w ork again ap p ro x im ate ly in th e sam e in sta n t of tim e, viz. w h en th e distance r D яь r B is attain ed . The tim e scale is v e ry m uch sim ilar to th a t obtained in Sec. 3 for th e harm onic oscilator: it begings a t t B, th e tim e w hen th e distance r B w as m easured, a n d ends a t t D, th e tim e w h en th e distance r D w as attain ed . The to ta lity of th e m easu­ rem e n ts rep re sen ts th e life of i.o. a n d — since th e system is

(7)

fu lly periodic — a c irc u la r Scale of tim e should be applied. The i.o. cannot d etect th a t t D æ t B.

Now let us introd u ce an e x te rn al observer (e.o.) w ith resp ect to th e in te rn a l one; the e.o. can m easu re m ore kinds of p a­ ra m e te rs th a n i.o. We assum e also th a t e.o. can rea d th e m easu rem en ts of i.o. b u t n o t vice versa. For exam ple, besides th e distance r = |S Z | th e e.o. can m easu re th e angle of th e direction SZ in resp ect to certain co n stan t direction SA w hich lin k s sun S w ith some s ta r A; see Fig. 3. If th e re is no precession of th e ellipse ab o u t th e ax is p e rp e n d icu la r to the ellipse plan e and going th ro u g h th e point S, th e angles

θ = <£ASZ (8)

m easu red in each course of Z abou t S w ill re p e a t exactly. L e t us assum e th e percep tio n of e.o. is sw itched on at th e angle

Hm = (<ïASZ)m (7) w hich is th e angle b etw een SA and SZ in th e case of

|sz|

= r min. (8) If ε" and ε " are in fin itesim ally sm all nu m bers, th e firs t m ea­ su re m e n t gives certain

C ' ·θ* = * . + « " (9)

an d th e last m easu rem en t gives certain

aD. = am+ 2K -e"',

(10)

because th e n e x t m ea su rem e n t of ϋ· is # B providing w e assum e th e e a rth m ovem ent a n d th e ry th m of the m easu rem en ts a re fu lly periodic. So th e life of e.o., though ric h e r th a n th e life of i.o. by th e set of m easu rem en ts of â b e ttw e e n $ B an d i?D, has th e tim e scale identical to th a t of i.o.

Now le t us assum e th e ellipse p erform s a slow precession in its plane. The life of i.o. does not change, b u t e.o. m ay now see a n d label d iffe re n t lives of i.o. This is so because th e a n g le -&m, th ere fo re th e w hole set of th e observed angles b etw een # B an d ê D, is now d iffe re n t for an y course of Z about S. T h e distinction b etw een two d iffe re n t courses allow s e.o. to discover th a t th e n e x t course of Z abo ut S begins im m edia­ tely a fte r th e end of th e fo rm er course. This m eans a p ro p e rty ■of th e system (precession) accom panied by th e corresponding

(8)

increase of th e ab ility to do m easu rem en ts (angles i9), m ake th e tim e scale of e.o. d iffe re n t th an th e tim e scale of i.o. We m ay assum e, for exam ple, th a t precession of th e ellipse covers a fu ll angle 2π ex actly durin g v courses of Z ab o u t S. Then e.o. w ill discover th a t his life is v tim es longer th a n the life of i.o. B ut q u alitativ ely , the tim e scale of e.o. rem ain s th e sam e as th a t of i.o., w hich m eans th a t th e scale of e.o. is also of a c irc u la r shaipe. T his is so because a fte r th e precession covered a fu ll angle 2π th e set of th e m easu rem en ts obtained b y e.o. rep eats ex actly 5. The e.o. cannot discover th is re p e ti­ tio n by him self, b u t th is can be done b y a n o th e r observer, le t us call him e.e.o., an d h aving a la rg e r ab ility fo r doing m easu rem en ts th a n e.o.; sim ultaneously, th e change of a new physical p a ra m e te r is necessary. F or exam ple, the system Z, S and A is a p a r t of a galaxy. We assum e th e plane ZSA on w hich Z, S an d A a re placed, ro ta te s ab ou t th e axis SA. We assum e e.e.o. is connected w ith the ro ta tin g system and — beyond r an d & ■— he can m easu re th e ro ta tio n angle φ of the p lan e ZSA ab o u t SA. Then e.e.o. w ill discover th a t d iffe re n t fu ll precessions of th e ellipse end a t d iffe re n t positions of the p lane ZSA. So e.e.o. has his ow n tim e scale, larg e r th a n th a t of e.o. The e.e.o. m ay count d iffe re n t fu ll precessions and discover th a t th e end of one life of e.o. is im m ed iately follow ed b y his — e.o. — n e x t life.

We sum m arize th is section by concluding th a t the tim e scale of an observ er connected w ith a m echanical sytem m ay depend both on his m easu ring ab ility and th e physical p ro p erties of th e system . If th e notion of th e observer is dropped out, we m ay speak ab o u t a convenient tim e scale for a system . A set of m easu rem en ts can be p erfo rm ed on a sy stem and th e tim e scale for an y system can be dep en d en t on this set.

5. PER T U R B A T IO N OF A Q U A N T U M -M EC H A N IC A L SY STEM A N D TO POLO GY OF TIM E

In n o n -relativ istic m echanics, both classic a n d q u antum , a s tra ig h t-lin e a r tim e scale is u su ally assum ed; Fig. 1. In preceding sections w e considered some m echanical system s an d gave arg u m e n ts for a d iffe re n t th a n linear, n am ely c ir­ cular, scale of tim e; Fig. 2. In fact, th e topology of the tim e scale is, to a larg e ex ten t, a m a tte r of convenience. A w

ell-5 L. D. L andau, E. M. L ifszits, Mechanics, Vol. 1 of C ourse o f T h e o r e ­

(9)

-kn o w n problem of sim ilar n a tu re concerned spatial coordina­ tes a n d was given in astronom y: th e p lan ets m ovem ent can be described eq ually in th e Ptolem aic, or geocentric, system as w ell as in th e Coperniean, or heliocentric, system , b u t the second sy stem is m ore co n ven ien t th an the first. The purpose of the rem a in d e r of th is p a p e r is to exam ine th e topology of the tim e scale fo r a n on -relativ istic q u antu m -m ech anical system . To th is p u rp o se w e choose th e problem of a p e rtu rb a tio n of a n o n -d eg en erate sta tio n a ry sta te of a q u an tu m -m ech anical system .

If th e system is in its sta tio n a ry state, no m ea su rem e n t do­ ne for it can provide a distinction b etw een a la te r an d an ea rlie r in sta n t of tim e, see Sec. 1. In fact, for such a system th e notion of tim e looses its sense. In re a lity th e sta tio n a ry sta te s on only a few q u an tu m -m ech an ical system s a re exactly know n. To such system s belong, fo r exam ple, a p article in th e field of a co n stan t poten tial, th e harm onic oscillator, and th e sta te s of th e no n -relativ istic hydro gen atom (athough in description of th e last tw o cases some special functions are necessary). We often seek for states w hich differ only slig h tly fro m th e e x a ctly know n states, for exam ple sta te s of th e h y d ro ­ gen ato m in th e w eak electric or m agnetic e x te rn al field. The sta te s w h ich a re w ell-k n o w n a re called u n p e rtu rb ed , w hereas sta te s obtained from the action of a su p p le m e n ta ry field a re called p e rtu rb e d states. S chrödinger gave a m ath em atical p ro ­ ce d u re w hich leads fro m u n p e rtu rb e d to p e rtu rb e d s t a t e s s. This is a com plicated ite ra tiv e process w hich re p re se n ts the p e rtu rb e d energies an d p e rtu rb e d w ave functio ns as a com bi­ n atio n of series based on th e u n p e rtu rb e d q u antities. Ite ra tio n m eans th a t contrib u tion s of th e n e x t step (higher order) can be ex pressed successively by those obtained in a fo rm e r step (low er order). This m akes th e w hole calculation e x tre m e ly com plicated an d in p ractice lim ited to only a few steps, on condition th a t w e assum e th a t re su lts calculated in these few steps ad e q u ate ly ap p ro x im ate th e ex act solutions.

A m ore system atic ap proach to th e p e rtu rb a tio n m ethod can be done on th e basis of field th eo ry \ A lthough w e look fo r a p e rtu rb e d sta tio n a ry state, th e tim e p a ra m e te r is in tro ­

8 L. I. S ch iff, Quantum, M echan ics, 3rd ed., M cG raw H ill, N e w Y ork 1968.

7 S. R aim es, M a n y - e le c t r o n T h e o r y , N orth -H ollan d P ubl. Comp,, A m sterd am 1972.

(10)

duced into th e calculation. This iparam eter is tak en along the lin ear scale of tim e. L et us consider th e sta te of a system w hich has th e low est energy, so it is called the gro un d state. It is assum ed th a t a t tim e t being v e ry far in the past ( t = — oo) th e sta te w as u n p e rtu rb e d w h ereas now ( t= 0 ) it is p ertu rb ed . T here is an o p erato r (the tim e-developm ent operator) w hich leads from the situ atio n a t t = — oo to th a t a t t = 0 . The in te rac tio n o p erators a re th e p e rtu rb a tio n ope­ ra to rs rep re sen te d in the so-called in te rac tio n p ictu re and ordered w ith th e help of the chronological operator. The sense of this last o p erato r is th a t it a rra n g e s th e sequence of the in teractio n op erato rs from th e e a rlie r to th e late r tim es. So, for exam ple, the p ro d u ct H A (ti) H B (ta) of tw o in te r­ action operators does not change on condition ti > U, b u t changes upon th e action of th e chronological op erato r into Hb (ta) H A (ti) if ta > ti. The in te rv als of th e in te g ratio n p e r­ fo rm ed over th e tim e v ariab les ex te n d from — oo to zero; therefo re, th ey correspond to a half of th e scale given in Fig. 1. The tim e-d ev elo p m en t op erato r obtained in th e above w ay can be av eraged over th e u n p e rtu rb e d w ave fun ction of the gro u n d state. T he im ag in ary p a rt of th e tim e derivative of the lo g arithm of th is average re p re se n ts exactly th e cor­ rection to th e energy of the u n p e rtu rb e d state, so w h en added to this energy, th e co rrection gives th e energy of th e p e r­ tu rb e d state. Such a tre a tm e n t, alth o u g h elegant, seem s to m ake th e p e rtu rb a tio n calculation still m ore laborious th an the S chrödinger ite rativ e procedure. Especially, the tre a tm e n t does no t give a clear in sig h t into how d iffe re n t com ponents term s (su m s),. en terin g th e S chrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n series, can be obtained. This situ atio n changes, how ever, w hen a cir­ c u la r scale of tim e — sim ilar to th a t given in Fig. 2 — is tak en into account instead of the lin e a r scale. This k in d of p e rtu rb a tio n th eo ry has been p rese n ted in some detail else­ w h e re 8. In the n e x t two sections w e outline those of its fe a tu re s w hich seem to be im p o rta n t from th e poin t of view

of the topology of tim e.

8 S. O lszew ski, T i m e Scale and, i t s A p p li c a ti o n in P e r tu r b a ti o n

(11)

6. PER T U R B A T IO N ENERGY O BT A IN E D FROM A C IRC ULA R SCALE OF TIM E

The tim e evolution of a q u an tu m -m ech anical system w hich goes on according to th e circu lar scale of tim e can be r e ­ p rese n ted by cycles of collisions of this system done w ith some p e rtu rb a tio n p o ten tial V.

We assum e th a t a system w hich is o riginally in a sta tio n ­ a ry s ta te n is tra n sfe re d u n d e r th e action of th e firs t collision in a cycle w ith th e p o ten tial V into some o th er s ta te p. A fter a su fficiently long tim e, sta te p can be considered as sta tio n ­ a ry sim ilarly to n. It is convenient to assum e th a t in sta te n th e system is ch aracterized by its own tim e v ariable t„, in sta te p th e system has its ow n tim e v ariab le tD, etc. Con­ sequ en tly , th e collision w ith V changes t n into tp. A n o th er collision tra n sfe rs th e system from a sta tio n a ry sta te p to a sta tio n a ry sta te q; th en th e tim e v ariab le t„ is changed into t„. F u r th e r collisions w ith V can tra n s fe r th e system to s ta te r, sta te s, etc.; accordingly, th e tim e p a ra m e te r w ill assum e th e tim e v ariab les tr, ts, etc. The last collision in a cycle is n ecessarily th a t w hich tra n sfe rs th e system back into sta te n. The n e x t collision w ith V begins a n ew cycle. The n u m b er of cycles is u n lim ited and tend s to in fin ity . A n exam ple of a cycle composed of fou r collisions (th ree in te r ­ m ed iate collisions) is rep re sen te d in Fig. 4.

A ny collision gives its co n trib u tio n to th e energy change of th e system . This change is p ro p ortio nal to th e in teg ral of the p ro d u ct of (a) th e com plex co njugate of th e w av e fu n c ­ tion of th e system before collision, (b) the p e rtu rb a tio n po­ ten tial, (c) th e w ave fu n ctio n a fte r collision. The in te g ratio n is perfo rm ed over the position-dependent, or spatial, as well as th e tim e-d ep en d en t coordinates. A ny collision defines th e space and tim e variab les over w hich th e in te g ratio n has to be done. In general, th e re s u lt of the succesive in tegrations, corresponding to succesive collisions, tends to zero. The ex ­ ception is th e situ atio n w hen a cycle ends w ith some col­ lision w hich tran sfo rm s th e system back to its in itial sta te n. We say th en th a t a cycle is closed and th en w e obtain a non - -zero co n trib u tio n to energy know n from th e S chrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n theory.

The in teg rals over space and tim e can be separated. The re s u lt of th e in te g ratio n over tim e for a (closed) cycle of collisions w e call a k in etic p a rt, w hereas a sim ilar in teg ral done over space v ariab les in a cycle is called a static p a rt.

(12)

In o rd er to get d iffe re n t contrib utio n s to th e S chröd ing er p e rtu rb a tio n energy, th e system m u st be su b m itte d to d if­ fe re n t (closed) cycles of collisions w hich begin an d end a t sta te n. The n u m b er of collisions in a cycle corresponds w ith th e o rd er of. th e S chrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n te rm . If th e tim e evolution in the collision cycle is re p re se n te d by a non- -b ran ch ed p ath , th e n w e obtain only one S chrödinger term for each p e rtu rb a tio n order. This is no t a satisfacto ry state of affairs, since for any p e rtu rb a tio n o rd er larg e r th a n 2 th e n u m b er of th e S chrödinger term s (sums) is larg e r th a n u n ity; for a high p e rtu rb a tio n o rder th is excess in the n u m b er of term s becomes v ery high. In o rd er to g et a correct n u m b er of the S chrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n term s, b ran ch ed p a th s of the tim e evolution of a system during its collision cycle should be as­ sum ed. G raphically th e n o n-b ran ch ed tim e p a th for a cycle can be rep re sen te d by a single loop (circle), called a m ain loop, w h ereas the b ran ch ed tim e p ath s are composed of se­ v e ra l loops, called side loops, w hich sprin g out of th e tim e loop having th e begin n ing -en d sta te n. The b ran ch ed tim e p ath s can be obtained w ith th e aid of th e elim ination p rin ­ ciple discussed in Sec. 7.

L et us note th a t in o rd er to get a c o rre c t rep re sen ta tio n of S ch rö d in g er’s re su lt for p e rtu rb a tio n energy, all collision cycles have to be d ifferent, e ith e r in th e ir shape or in the indices w hich label the sta te s m et in th e collisions. A r e ­ petitio n of a cycle g iv es.n o co n trib u tion to energy.

7. ELIM IN ATIO N PR IN C IPLE FOR E Q U A L TIM ES

In q u a n tu m m echanics of m an y -electro n system s w e have a principle given by P auli w hich m akes referen ce to sy m ­ m e try p ro p erties of th e w ave fun ctio n of the system . If the w ave fun ctio n of a m an y -electro n system is ap p ro x im ated by a com bination of p ro d ucts of th e one-electron w ave fu n c ­ tions th e P au li principle becom es an exclusion principle w hich states th a t an y o n e-electron w ave function cannot be occupied by m ore th an one electron. The exclusion principle is of a fu n d am en tal im portance for describing physical and chem ical p ro p erties of m atte r. H istorically, the ex p lan atio n of th e periodic system of elem ents, as w ell as th e electric an d th erm al p ro p ertie s of m etals, re p re se n te d its firs t suc­ cess. The assu m p tio n th a t electrons in a system behave like iden tical p articles w as also a t the basis of th e principle.

A lthough p hysically it has a com pletely d iffe re n t sense,

(13)

th e fo rm u latio n of th e elim ination p rin ciple in this p a p e r h a s some sim ilarities to th a t of th e P a u li principle. T he elim ina­ tion prin cip le concerns th e tim e in sta n ts of collisions w ith V a n d sta te s th a t th e en erg y co n trib u tio n given by any cycle in w hich the system has two or m ore sim u ltan eo us collisions w ith V should be su b tra c te d from th e p e rtu rb a tio n energy. A t th e sam e tim e, w e p o stu late th a t th e static p a rt of tw o cycles h av ing th e sam e p a tte rn of collisions w ith V a re identical in d ep en d en tly of th a t w h e th e r a cycle is re p re s e n t­ ed by a m ain loop, or a side loop of tim e.

In applying th e elim ination principle, as w ell as the po­ stu la te of id e n tity for the static p arts, the beginning-end sta te n is considered in a d iffe re n t w ay th an the in te rm e d ia te sta te s in a cycle. F irst, th e ow n tim e of sta te n can nev er be equal to th e ow n tim e of an in te rm e d ia te state; second, the beg inn ing -end sta te for an y static p a rt in a cycle re ­ p rese n ted by a side loop should be p u t equal to sta te n. T his eq u ality m akes th e begin n ing -end sta te for a static p a rt th e sam e fo r all cycles.

The elim ination principle n eed s to lau n ch a com binatorial analysis for a n y collision cycle. This analysis has, as its p u r­ pose, to select all cases for w hich th e in te rm e d ia te collision tim es can be equal. Two or m ore equal collision tim es divide th e original (main) loop of tim e into tw o or m ore loops. For. exam ple, for a cycle w hich has th re e in te rm e d ia te collisions (rep resen ted by a loop on Fig. 4) w e can have th e follow ing cases of equal tim es: th e collision in sta n t 1 is sim ultaneous w ith collision in sta n t 2; collision in 1 is sim ultaneou s w ith th a t in 3; collision 2 is sim u ltan eou s w ith 3; fin ally w e can h ave sim u ltaneo usly all th re e in te rm e d ia te collisions (in stan ts 1, 2, 3). The colon on Fig. 5— 5c re p re se n ts a sym bol of equal tim es. A n im p o rta n t p o in t is th a t an y tw o tim es, w h en p u t equal on a given p ath , should give loops w hich m ay touch; b u t no crossing of th e tim e p a th is allow ed. F or exam ple, a p a th is n o t allow ed on w hich sim u ltan eou s tim e a re select­ ed in th e w ay re p re se n te d in Fig. 6. The allow ed k in d of selection of the tim e p a th s im plies th a t the sequence of col­ lision tim es w ith V should be preserv ed . If w e p u t collision tim e 1 equal to tim e 3, th e n tim e 2 (w hich is in te rm e d ia te b etw een 1 an d 3) cann o t be equal to tim e 4 w h ich is la te r th a n 3.

The elim ination p rin cip le can lead to tim e p a th s composed of m an y loops. F o r exam ple, fo r a cycle of fo u r in te rm e d ia te

(14)

collisions, w h ere a collision tim e 1 is p u t equal to collision tim e 4, we obtain a p a th rep re sen te d by tw o loops. H ow ever, the elim ination principle req u ires also to tak e into account th e case of tim e 2 equal to tim e 3 on th e p a th given on the r ig h t side of Fig. 7. This leads to th e p a th rep re sen te d in Fig. 7a an d a sep arate Schrödinger term corresponding to it is attain ed ,

A consequent application of the elim ination principle, to­ g e th e r w ith th e p o stu la te of id en tity of th e static p arts, gives a full set of term s of the Schrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n series for energy. The sign w ith w hich the term s e n te r th e series is also given by th e elim ination principle. Two collision tim es assu m ed equal on a given n on -b ran ch ed p a th m eans th a t the re su lte d term has to be su b tra c te d from the te rm re p re s e n t­ ing th e cycle having a n o n-b ran ch ed p ath . F or exam ple, th re e collision tim es assum ed equal together, can be considered as com ing from a p a th of tw o equal collision tim es, so th e re su lt fo r th re e equal collision tim es should be su b tra c te d from, th a t obtained for tw o equal collision tim es, etc.

8. SU R V EY

In this p ap er w e ex am ined a problem of th e topology of th e tim e scale. As an a lte rn a tiv e to an open, or linear, scale th e re a re p re se n te d arg u m e n ts for a closed, or circular, scale of tim e.

As th e firs t step, w e p o in ted out th a t the tim e scale can be a sub jective notion d ep en d en t on th e physical p ro p erties of a given system an d th e percep tio n a b ility of an o bserver connected w ith th a t system . In a fu lly periodic classical sy ­ stem , th e re is no p a ra m e te r w hich allow s for an observer to distinguish b etw een one cycle of ev en ts (observations) and a n o th e r cycle. In this case th e c ircu lar scale tim e is n a tu ra lly fitte d to th e periodic p ro p ertie s of th e system . The len g th of th e scale m ay d epend on: (i) the n u m b er a n d k in d of p a ra ­ m ete rs ch aracterizin g th e system , (ii) th e p ercep tio n ab ility of a n o bserver. In th e case of a langer scale boith (i) and (ii) a re la rg e r th a n in the case of a sh o rte r scale. O nly an obser­ v e r lin a periodic system h aving a la rg e r scale c a n detect th e periodicity of a sy stem having a sh o rte r scale.

As a second step, in o rd er to have an idea ab o u t th e topo­ logy of th e tim e scale for m icrophysical system s, th is topo­ logy w as ex am ined for a n o n -d eg en erate q u antu m -m echanical system p e rtu rb e d by a sm all poten tial. It is p o in ted o u t th a t

(15)

the S ch rö d in g er p e rtu rb a tio n en erg y of this system can be obtained in a r a th e r sim ple w ay on condition th a t a circu lar scale of tim e is assum ed. B eginning w ith some u n p e rtu rb e d q u a n tu m state, th e system is su b m itted to a cycle of collis­ ions w ith th e p e rtu rb a tio n p o ten tial; a fte r th e last collision in a cycle th e system re tu r n to its beginnig sta te an d a new cycle of collisions begins. A n elim ination p rinciple is tak en into account in o rd er to su b tra c t th e co n tribu tion s given by th e cycles in w hich two or m ore sim ultaneous collisions w ith th e p o ten tial occur. W ith the aid of this principle th e re exists a s tric t correspondence b etw een th e colllision cycles a n d th e term s of the S chrödinger p e rtu rb a tio n series. On th e o th er hand , th e application of a lin e a r scale of tim e to a no n-dege­ n e ra te ground sta te can repro d u ce S ch rö d in g er’s th e o ry of p e rtu rb a tio n energy of a sy stem in a m uch m ore com plicated w ay.

I dedicate this pap er to th e m em ory of m y fa th e r, P aw el Olszewski, who stim u la te d m y in te re st in th e prob lem of tim e. I am g rate fu l to Tadeusz K w iatkow ski for his assistance in checking the com ponents of th e p e rtu rb a tio n series an d to Joseph A. D ziver for his collaboration in p rep a rin g the E nglish version of th e m an u script.

p --- » . --- F

(past)

(future)

Fig. 1. L in ear scale of tim e.

P

—---9---в

---

D

m

--- :

---/

s

/

\

/

\

---Z»------

*

---В

D

Fig. la , lb . L in ear scale of tim e for a cla ssica l p eriod ic system . В — th e first ob served p oin t; D — th e la st o b served p oin t. For a s tr ic tly periodic sy stem th e o b serv a tio n of D ta k es p la ce im m ed ia ­ t e ly b efo re th e ob servation B.

(16)

F ig. 2. C ircular sca le of tim e.

Fig. 3. T he m otion of Z a lo n g an e llip se about poin t S w h ich is in one o f th e e llip s e foci. T he d ashed orbit rep resen ts p recessio n o f the e llip s e a b ou t th e a x is goin g across S and b ein g p erp en d icu lar to th e F ig u re p lane.

n

2

F ig. 4. A n ex a m p le o f a c y c le o f co llisio n s h a v in g th ree in term ed ia te c o llis io n s w ith th e p ertu rb ation p o te n tia l V.

(17)

O

2

1 = 3

n

Ô

3

2

= 1

1

:

2:3

F ig. 5— 5c. C ycles o f th ree in term ed ia te co llisio n s w ith p o ten tia l V in case w h en sim u lta n eo u s co llisio n s occur.

n

F ig. 6. A n ex a m p le o f a forb id d en set of sim u lta n eo u s co llisio n s for a cycle of fou r in term ed ia te collision s.

(18)

n

1 U

Rg .7

Fig. 7a

F ig . 7—7a. E x a m p les o f a llo w ed sets o f .sim ultaneous co llisio n s for a c y c le o f fou r in term ed ia te collision s.

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

frazeologią „narodowowyzwoleńczą”, co zbytnio dziwić nie może, bo na skutek ciągłego b rak u czasu na dłuższe zatrzym anie się nad każdą ważniejszą

In this work, we develop a family of analytical solutions for very simple topology optimiza- tion problems, in the framework of elasticity theory, including bending and extension

We will in particular consider statistical descriptions of dynamical systems in discrete time, where one tries to study the actual system in terms of a restricted class of

This definition enables us to extend in (Tokarzewski, 1998) the results of (El-Ghezawi et al., 1982) (where square strictly proper systems of uniform rank are analysed) on

I hereby request for re-admitting me to studies in order to submit my diploma thesis and take the diploma examination. I was removed from the student list

I hereby request for re-admitting me to studies in order to submit my diploma thesis and take the diploma examination. I was removed from the student list on...( state the

As for co-operation with institutions from outside Wielkopolska, the issues of the greatest signifi cance for company competitiveness were product improvement and increased

We then give an explicit example by showing that Lebesgue measure regarded as a function on the space of compact subsets of [0, 1], which is upper semicontinuous, is not