• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Abstract. We show that a set of reals is undetermined in Galvin’s point-open game iff it is uncountable and has property C

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Abstract. We show that a set of reals is undetermined in Galvin’s point-open game iff it is uncountable and has property C"

Copied!
7
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

144 (1994)

Undetermined sets of point-open games

by

Janusz P a w l i k o w s k i (Wrocław)

Abstract. We show that a set of reals is undetermined in Galvin’s point-open game iff it is uncountable and has property C

00

, which answers a question of Gruenhage.

Let X be a topological space. The point-open game G(X) of Galvin [G]

is played as follows. Black chooses a point x

0

∈ X, then White chooses an open set U

0

3 x

0

, then B chooses a point x

1

∈ X, then W chooses an open set U

1

3 x

1

, etc. B wins the play (x

0

, U

0

, x

1

, U

1

, . . .) iff X = S

n

U

n

.

Galvin [G] showed that the Continuum Hypothesis yields a Lusin set X which is undetermined (i.e. for which the game G(X) is undetermined). (A Lusin set is an uncountable set of reals which has countable intersection with every meager set.)

Recently Rec law [R] showed that every Lusin set is undetermined. Mo- tivated by Rec law’s result we prove the following.

Theorem. Let X be a topological space in which every point is G

δ

. Then G(X) is undetermined iff X is uncountable and has property C

00

.

Property C

00

was introduced by Rothberger (see [M]). A topological space X has property C

00

if for every sequence U

n

(n ∈ ω) of open covers of X there exist U

n

∈ U

n

such that X = S

n

U

n

. It is known (see [M] or [FM]) that every Lusin set has property C

00

.

Clearly, a space with property C

00

must be Lindel¨of. Martin’s Axiom im- plies that every Lindel¨of space of size less than 2

0

has property C

00

and that there are sets of reals of size 2

0

with property C

00

(see [M]). Thus, Martin’s Axiom yields undetermined sets of reals of size 2

0

(Theorem 4 of [G]).

On the other hand, in Laver’s [L] model for Borel’s conjecture all metric spaces with property C

00

are countable (see Note 1). Thus, consistently, all metric spaces are determined.

1991 Mathematics Subject Classification: 03E15, 54G15.

Supported by KBN grant PB 2 1017 91 01.

(2)

The connection between property C

00

and point-open games is made transparent by the following dual game G

(X), due also to Galvin [G]. Now W chooses an open cover U

0

of X, then B chooses a set U

0

∈ U

0

, then W chooses an open cover U

1

of X, then B chooses a set U

1

∈ U

1

, etc. As before, B wins if X = S

n

U

n

.

Galvin [G] showed that the games G(X) and G

(X) are equivalent in the sense that W ↑ G(X) (has a winning strategy) iff W ↑ G

(X); similarly for B. In particular, G(X) is determined iff G

(X) is.

Let G

σ

(X) and G

∗σ

(X) be games that are played as G(X) and G

(X) are, but in which B wins if X = T

n

S

m>n

U

m

. These games are again equivalent (see [G], Theorem 1). Clearly, |X| ≤ ℵ

0

⇒ B ↑ G

∗σ

(X) ⇒ B ↑ G

(X), and it is not hard to see that if each point of X is G

δ

, then B ↑ G

(X) ⇒ |X| ≤ ℵ

0

(see [G], Theorem 2). Also, X 6∈ C

00

⇒ W ↑ G

(X) ⇒ W ↑ G

∗σ

(X) (for the first implication W plays covers that witness X 6∈ C

00

).

We shall prove that W ↑ G

∗σ

(X) ⇒ X 6∈ C

00

.

First let us play one more game. The game M

(X) is defined as G

(X) is but B chooses finite subsets V

n

⊆ U

n

. He wins if S

n

S V

n

= X. The σ is introduced as before.

The game is motivated by property M of Menger (see [FM]). A topolog- ical space has property M if for every sequence U

n

(n ∈ ω) of open covers of X there exist finite V

n

⊆ U

n

such that S

n

S V

n

= X. Clearly, property C

00

implies property M .

Lemma 1. Suppose that X has property M. Then W has no winning strategy in M

∗σ

(X).

P r o o f. X is clearly Lindel¨of. Without loss of generality, we can assume that W plays increasing sequences from which B chooses single sets. Then a strategy for W can be identified with a family {U

σ

: σ ∈

ω} such that for every σ, {U

σ_i

: i < ω} is an increasing open cover of X. We seek s ∈

ω

ω such that ∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ U

s|n

.

For integers j > 0 and k, m ≥ 0 let V

k

(m, j) = \

τ ∈mj

U

τ_k

.

Note that {V

k

(m, j) : k ∈ ω} is an increasing open cover of X: given x ∈ X, find k

τ

(τ ∈

m

j) with x ∈ U

τ_kτ

and let k = max

τ

k

τ

; then x ∈ V

k

(m, j).

For integers j > 0, k ≥ j and m, n ≥ 0 let W

kn

(m, j) = [

j=k0≤k1≤...≤kn+1=k

\

n i=0

V

ki+1

(m + i, k

i

) .

Again {W

kn

(m, j) : k ≥ j} is an increasing open cover of X: given x ∈ X,

find k

1

≥ k

0

with x ∈ V

k1

(m, k

0

), next k

2

≥ k

1

with x ∈ V

k2

(m + 1, k

1

),

(3)

etc. So, {W

kn

(m, j) : k ≥ j} (n ∈ ω) is a sequence of open covers, and, since X ∈ M , there is t

m,j

ω

ω such that

∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ W

tnm,j(n)

(m, j) .

Let s ∈

ω

ω be strictly increasing such that ∀m, j ∀

n s(m + n) ≥ t

m,j

(n).

Then

∀x ∈ X ∀m , j ∃n x ∈ W

s(m+n)n

(m, j) . Claim. ∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ U

s|n

.

P r o o f. Suppose not. Fix x and m with ∀n x 6∈ U

s|(m+n)

. By the choice of s there is n with x ∈ W

s(m+n)n

(m, s(m)). So, there are integers

s(m) = k

0

≤ k

1

≤ . . . ≤ k

n+1

= s(m + n) such that

x ∈

\

n i=0

V

ki+1

(m + i, k

i

).

Now, s|m ∈

m

k

0

, x ∈ V

k1

(m, k

0

) and x 6∈ U

s|m_s(m)

yield k

1

> s(m). Next, s|(m + 1) ∈

(m+1)

k

1

, x ∈ V

k2

(m + 1, k

1

) and x 6∈ U

s|(m+1)_s(m+1)

yield k

2

> s(m + 1). Proceeding in this way we get k

n+1

> s(m + n), which is a contradiction.

It follows that if W plays according to {U

σ

: σ ∈

ω} and B according to s, then B wins.

Now we prove that if X ∈ C

00

then B can spoil each strategy of W in G

∗σ

(X). The idea of diagonalization used in the proof is taken from [FM], Lemma 5.1.

Lemma 2. Suppose that X has property C

00

. Then W has no winning strategy in G

∗σ

(X).

P r o o f. Again X is Lindel¨of and we can identify a strategy for W with a family {U

σ

: σ ∈

ω} of open sets such that ∀σ X = S

i

U

σ_i

. We seek s ∈

ω

ω such that ∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ U

s|n

.

For integers j > 0, m ≥ 0 and for σ : j

m

7→ ω let U

σ

(m, j) = \

τ ∈mj

[ {U

τ_σ|i

: 0 < i ≤ j

m

}.

B is sure to cover this set if from round m on he plays according to σ, provided so far he has played numbers < j.

Claim 1. ∀m, j U

σ

(m, j)’s form an open cover of X.

P r o o f. Fix m and j. Let x ∈ X be given. Let hτ

k

: k < j

m

i be an

enumeration of

m

j. Define σ by induction: choose σ(0) so that x ∈ U

τ0_σ(0)

,

next choose σ(1) so that x ∈ U

τ1_σ(0)_σ(1)

, etc.

(4)

Claim 2. There are increasing sequences hj

n

: n < ωi, hm

n

: n < ωi of integers such that

∀x ∈ X ∃

n ∃ σ : (m

n+1

− m

n

) 7→ j

n+1

x ∈ U

σ

(m

n

, j

n

) .

P r o o f. Let j

0

= 1, m

0

= 0. We start a game. At the nth round, j

n

and m

n

are given and W plays an open cover

U

σ

(m

n

, j

n

) (σ : j

nmn

7→ ω) .

B responds with an integer j

n+1

≥ j

n

, but really thinks about S

{U

σ

(m

n

, j

n

) : max

i

σ(i) < j

n+1

}. Then he declares m

n+1

= m

n

+ j

nmn

.

We view this as the M

∗σ

(X) game played by W according to a fixed strategy. Since C

00

⇒ M , by Lemma 1, B can spoil this strategy.

For k

1

< . . . < k

n

< ω and σ

i

: (m

ki+1

− m

ki

) 7→ j

ki+1

define W (k

1

, . . . , k

n

; σ

1

, . . . , σ

n

) =

\

n i=1

U

σi

(m

ki

, j

ki

) .

By Claim 2 we see that for every n, W (k

1

, . . . , k

n

; σ

1

, . . . , σ

n

)’s form an open cover of X. Since X ∈ C

00

, there are σ

ni

, k

ni

(n = 1, 2, . . . ; i = 1, . . . , n) such that

∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ W (k

n1

, . . . , k

nn

; σ

1n

, . . . , σ

nn

) .

Let l

n

∈ {k

1n

, . . . , k

nn

} \ {k

n−11

, . . . , k

n−1n−1

} and let τ

n

be the σ

in

corre- sponding to l

n

. Then l

n

’s are distinct and, by the definition of W ’s, we get

∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ U

τn

(m

ln

, j

ln

) . Now define s ∈

ω

ω by

s(m

ln

+ i) = τ

n

(i) , for n ∈ ω and i ∈ dom(τ

n

), and put 0 elsewhere.

Claim 3. ∀x ∈ X ∃

n x ∈ U

s|n

.

P r o o f. If x ∈ U

τn

(m

ln

, j

ln

) then, since s|m

ln

: m

ln

7→ j

ln

, we get x ∈ [

{U

s|mln_τn|i

: 0 < i ≤ m

ln+1

− m

ln

} . But s|m

ln_

τ

n

|i = s|(m

ln

+ i).

It follows that if W plays according to {U

σ

: σ ∈

ω} and B plays according to s, then B wins.

Call an open cover U of X strong if for each U ∈ U, the family {V ∈ U : U ⊆ V } covers X. Galvin showed that for a regular space X, W ↑ G(X) iff no strong open cover contains an increasing subcover {U

n

: n ∈ ω}

([GT], Theorem 4). Combining Galvin’s theorem with ours we can give a

characterization of regular C

00

spaces. By a covering tree we mean a family

(5)

T of finite sequences σ = hU

0

, . . . , U

n−1

i (n ∈ ω) of open subsets of X such that ∀σ ∈ T ∀k < |σ| σ|k ∈ T and ∀σ ∈ T {U : σ

_

U ∈ T } covers X.

Proposition 1. Let X be a regular topological space. Then the following are equivalent.

(a) X has property C

00

.

(b) In every covering tree there exists a branch hU

n

: n ∈ ωi with S

n

U

n

= X (equivalently, with T

m

S

n>m

U

n

= X).

(c) In every strong open cover there exists an increasing subcover {U

n

: n ∈ ω}.

P r o o f (cf. [GT], Theorem 4). (a)⇒(b) follows by Lemma 2. (b)⇒(c) is easy: given a strong open cover, use increasing finite sequences of its members as a covering tree.

We shall show (c)⇒(a). Assume (c). First, X is Lindel¨of. Otherwise any finitely additive open cover with no countable subcover violates (c). Also, X is zerodimensional (has a clopen base). Indeed, there is no continuous function f from X onto [0, 1] (otherwise {f

−1

[V ] : V ⊆ [0, 1] open with [0, 1]\V uncountable} violates (c)). For completely regular spaces this means having a clopen base, and X, being Lindel¨of regular, is completely regular.

Now, let U

n

(n ∈ ω) be a sequence of open covers of X. Since X is Lindel¨of and zerodimensional, we can assume that each U

n

is countable and consists of pairwise disjoint clopens (see [K], §26).

Let U

n

= {U

in

: i < ω} (some U

in

’s may be empty). Define f : X 7→

ω

ω by

f (x)(n) = i iff x ∈ U

in

. Let V = S

{U

in

: |f [U

in

]| ≤ ℵ

0

}. Then |f [V ]| ≤ ℵ

0

and since ∀x ∈ X x ∈ T

n

U

f (x)(n)n

, it is not hard to see that there exist t

2n+1

∈ ω (n ∈ ω) with V ⊆ T

n

U

t2n+12n+1

. Suppose that X \ V 6= ∅ (otherwise we are done). We can easily refine the covers U

2n

(with the help of U

2m

’s, m ≥ n) to covers W

n

so that W

n+1

is a refinement of W

n

and each W ∈ W

n

which meets X \ V contains at least two sets from W

n+1

which meet X \ V .

Let V

σ

= V ∪ S

n<|σ|

W

σ(n)n

for σ ∈

ω such that each W

σ(n)n

meets X \ V . Then V

σ

’s constitute a strong open cover of X. Also, if V

σ

⊆ V

τ

then σ ⊆ τ (because no W

kn

which meets X \ V can be covered by finitely many sets taken from different W

m

(m > n)).

It follows that from an increasing sequence of V

σ

’s covering X, which exists by (c), we get s ∈

ω

ω with X \ V ⊆ S

n

W

s(n)n

. Since there are t

2n

(n ∈ ω) with W

s(n)n

⊆ U

t2n2n

, we get X ⊆ S

n

U

tnn

.

Rothberger also considered property C

0

, which is defined as C

00

is but

the covers U

n

are finite. We can define a game corresponding to C

0

by

(6)

introducing to G

the requirement that the covers played by W are finite.

Then an analogue of Lemma 2 is true (see the proof of (a)⇒(b) below). We also have the following. (A tree is finitely branching if the set of immediate successors of any node is finite.)

Proposition 2. Let X be a regular topological space. Then the following are equivalent.

(a) X has property C

0

.

(b) In every finitely branching covering tree there exists a branch hU

n

: n ∈ ωi with S

n

U

n

= X (equivalently, with T

m

S

n>m

U

n

= X).

(c) In every strong open cover U such that for each U ∈ U, a finite subfamily of {V ∈ U : U ⊆ V } covers X, there exists an increasing subcover {U

n

: n ∈ ω}.

P r o o f. We sketch (a)⇒(b); (b)⇒(c)⇒(a) are proved as in Proposition 1.

Suppose that X ∈ C

0

. Let T be a finitely branching covering tree. For each n ∈ ω, let V

n

be a common finite refinement of all covers U

σ

=

df

{U : σ

_

U ∈ T } (σ ∈ T and |σ| = n). Such a refinement exists because there are only finitely many covers to refine. Since X ∈ C

0

there is a sequence V

n

∈ V

n

such that X = T

m

S

n>m

V

n

. Define a branch hU

n

: n ∈ ωi of T by U

n

= any U ⊇ V

n

such that hU

0

, . . . , U

n−1

, U i ∈ T .

N o t e. 1. It is folklore that every metric space X ∈ C

00

is homeomorphic to a subspace of R (the reals). Such an X is zerodimensional (it cannot be continuously mapped onto [0, 1] as C

00

is preserved by continuous images and [0, 1] 6∈ C

00

; [K], §40). Being Lindel¨of, X is separable, and so homeomorphic to a subset of

ω

ω. Since every C

00

set of reals has strong measure zero, Borel’s conjecture implies that every C

00

metric space is countable.

2. In the spirit of [R], X ⊆ R with property C

00

can be characterized by any of the following (see [P]):

(a) for any F

σ

(equivalently, closed) A ⊆ R

2

with all vertical sections A

x

(x ∈ X) meager, S

x∈X

A

x

6= R;

(b) for any closed A ⊆ R

2

with all vertical sections A

x

(x ∈ X) null, S

x∈X

A

x

is null.

Also, X ⊆ R has strong measure zero iff any of the following holds:

(a) for any F

σ

(equivalently, closed) A ⊆ R

2

with all vertical sections A

x

(x ∈ R) meager, S

x∈X

A

x

6= R ([AR]);

(b) for any closed A ⊆ R

2

with all vertical sections A

x

(x ∈ R) null, S

x∈X

A

x

is null ([P]);

(c) for any closed null D ⊆ R, X + D is null ([P]).

(7)

3. There exists (in ZFC) an uncountable C

00

space in which every point is G

δ

. Todorˇcević [T] has an example of a zerodimensional first countable Hausdorff space of size ℵ

1

whose every continuous image into any second countable space (in particular, into ω

ω

) is countable.

Question. In Propositions 1 and 2, can one remove the assumption that X is regular (it is used in (c)⇒(a))?

Acknowledgements. Thanks to Irek Rec law for inspiring correspon- dence and for communicating Gruenhage’s question.

References

[AR] A. A n d r y s z c z a k and I. R e c ł a w, A note on strong measure zero sets, to appear.

[FM] D. H. F r e m l i n and A. M i l l e r, On some properties of Hurewicz , Menger , and Rothberger, Fund. Math. 129 (1988), 17–33.

[G] F. G a l v i n, Indeterminacy of point-open games, Bull. Acad. Polon. Sci. 26 (1978), 445–449.

[GT] F. G a l v i n and R. T e l g ´a r s k y, Stationary strategies in topological games, Topol- ogy Appl. 22 (1986), 51–69.

[K] K. K u r a t o w s k i, Topology, Vol. 1, Academic Press, 1966.

[L] R. L a v e r, On the consistency of Borel’s conjecture, Acta Math. 137 (1976), 151–

169.

[M] A. W. M i l l e r, Special subsets of the real line, in: Handbook of Set-Theoretical Topology, K. Kunen and J. E. Vaughan (eds.), Elsevier, 1984, 203–233.

[P] J. P a w l i k o w s k i, Property C

00

, strongly meager sets and subsets of the plane, preprint.

[R] I. R e c ł a w, Every Lusin set is undetermined in the point-open game, Fund. Math.

144 (1994), 43–54.

[T] S. T o d o rˇce v i ć, On the Lindel¨of property of Aronszajn trees, in: General Topology and its Relation to Analysis and Algebra VI, Z. Frol´ık (ed.), Heldermann-Verlag, 1988, 577–588.

DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF WROCŁAW PL. GRUNWALDZKI 2

/

4 50-384 WROCŁAW, POLAND

E-mail: PAWLIKOW@PLWRUW11.BITNET

Received 27 April 1993;

in revised form 8 October 1993

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

A complete probability measure µ on a space X is said to be Radon if it is defined on the Borel subsets of X and has the property that the measure of each Borel set is the supremum

Recall that the covering number of the null ideal (i.e. Fremlin and has been around since the late seventies. It appears in Fremlin’s list of problems, [Fe94], as problem CO.

For infinite I, use Theorem 2.9 of [9], which says that if all the τ -additive topological product measures on finite subproducts are com- pletion regular, and all but countably many

Moreover, in Musielak–Orlicz sequence spaces, criteria for the Banach–Saks property, the near uniform convexity, the uniform Kadec–Klee property and property (H) are given... 1. Let

This indeed turned out to be the right approach since Baumgartner’s proof (see [3]) also shows that PFA implies that every uncountable subset of P(ω) contains an uncountable chain or

W i l k i e, Some model completeness results for expansions of the ordered field of real numbers by Pfaffian functions, preprint, 1991. [10] —, Model completeness results for

We show that any block of a group algebra of some finite group which is of wild representation type has many families of stable tubes.. The Auslander–Reiten quiver is an

We show that some classes of small sets are topological versions of some combinatorial properties.. We also give a characterization of spaces for which White has a winning strategy