• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

On Explaining the Trial of Galileo

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "On Explaining the Trial of Galileo"

Copied!
31
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)
(2)

Joseph Agassi (United States and Israel)

ON EXPLAINING THE TRIAL OF GALILEO 1

I f a s c i e n c e h a s t o b e s u p p o r t e d b y f r a u d u ­ l e n t m e a n s , l e t i t p e r i s h . ( J . K e p l e r ) T h e l i f e o f a g r e a t m a n .. . c a n n e v e r b e a m e r e r e c o r d o f u n d i s p u t e d f a c t . . . T h e b i o g r a p h e r . . . m u s t p e n e t r a t e b e h i n d m e r e e v e n t s t o t h e p u r p o s e a n d c h a r a c t e r t h e y d i s c l o s e , a n d c a n o n l y d o s o b y a n e f f o r t o f c o n s t r u c t i v e i m a g i n a t i o n . (A . E . T a y l o r ) T h e r e a r e n o v i l l a i n s i n t h e p i e c e ... I t i s w h a t m e n d o a t t h e i r b e s t , w i t h g o o d i n t e n t i o n s , t h a t r e a l l y c o n c e r n s u s ... i f J o a n h a d n o t b e e n b u r n t b y n o r m a l l y i n n o c e n t p e o p l e i n t h e e n e r g y o f t h e i r r i g h t e o u s n e s s , h e r d e a t h a t t h e i r h a n d s w o u l d h a v e n o m o r e s i g n i f i ­ c a n c e t h a n t h e T o k y o e a r t h q u a k e . .. (G . B . S h a w )

1. INTRODUCTION AND SUMMARY

A rth u r K oestler’s The Sleepw alkers is, the subtitle says, “a history of m an’s changing vision of the U niverse”. The thesis w hich this history illustrates, we are told, is th a t science and religion are essentially p a rt­ ners, sharing m ystic intuition as th eir common source. A dm ittedly, science and religion are now divided, b ut this division is m erely the outcome of some historical events—Galileo’s q u arrel w ith the C hurch

1 I am indebted to Professors J. Clark, S. J., F. Cronin, S. J., I. C. Jarvie, Sir Karl Popper, and G. de Santillana. None of them endorses all the view s here proposed. References are given only when it is not clear from the context to which work mentioned in the bibliography I am referring; numbers in brackets are page numbers of works named in the bibliography.

(3)

of Rome and the ensuing m isunderstandings—w hich could have been avoided; it is high time now to reunite science and faith, so as to save Man from (nuclear) selfdestruction. The m eat of the volume consists of two essays, one on K epler, one on Galileo. The form er is sym pathetic to­ w ards its hero and w as w ell-received, the la tter is critical of its hero and was frow ned upon. Prima facie, a t least, public opinion was rath e r apologetic.

K oestler’s view of Galileo has been violently attacked by two leading students of Galileo—S antillana and Drake. Many of their strictures are just; y et even if all of them w ere just, I would still dissent from their overall judgm ent. Though K oestler is no scholar, his w ork is of value. It contains valid criticism s of scholary works, and the first lively image of Galileo. K oestler’s great success is in managing the hum anization of an idol even though he did so at the expense of com m itting some serious errors.

Roman Catholic w riters have already claimed th a t the clash between Galileo and the C hurch was to this or th a t extent rooted in th ree faults of Galileo’s. First, his difficult personality; second, his m istakes in science w hich w ere corrected by la te r scientific studies; and, third, his attem pts to meddle w ith theology. Koestler, although his contem pt for the Inquisition is considerable, accepts these strictures, pushes all three as fa r as he can, and combines them into one: Galileo fought not for the sake of tru th , b u t because he was pathologically unable to avoid any quarrel, accept any compromise, or adm it any error. K oestler has succeeded in draw ing a new and very vivid picture of Galileo and of his trial, even though h ardly any of the accusations he levels against Galileo is claimed to be new, w ith the exception of th e attribution of motives. Now it is dangerous to a ttrib u te motives, especially low ones, and especially to an idol. Yet K oestler has rendered a valuable service in trying to do so, and not m erely because he m ay be viewed as the dev­ il’s advocate. We cannot explain historical events w ithout making hypoth­ eses concerning the aims, interests, and motives of those who have participated in them. And after we propose such explanatory hypothe­ ses, we can try to argue rationally about th eir tru th or falsity, and then improve on them. Galileo held th ree different positions in different times: first, he concealed his Copem icanism ; then—w hen he was about fifty—he defended it w ith some caution; his great battle for it took place w hen he was about seventy. K oestler’s view of Galileo’s motives and purpose is offered as one explanation of all theree phases: the young Galileo’s avoidance of open defence of Copernicanism was rooted in his knowledge th a t once he w ould be draw n into a controversy it would be a fierce and uncom prom ising battle. This self-awareness, says Koest­ ler, first m ade Galileo tim id; b u t once he fought he would not be stop­ ped. For m y part, I th ink the story of Galileo is not th a t of one and

(4)

the same character: the story of the old Galileo is the story of a changed m an—of a Catholic reform er who hoped to p revent fu rth e r clashes between science and Catholicism, b u t whose plan misfired.

2. KOESTLER AND HIS PREDECESSORS

The story of Galileo has two sides to it, one scientific, one political, which are closely related bu t very distinct. It has other sides as well, philosophical, theological, etc. These have not yet attracted th e attention th ey deserve. L et us, then, take the scientific side first and the political second. Most w riters on Galileo have taken it for granted th at scientif­ ically he was rig h t because he was a Copernican, and his opponents w ere w rong as they w ery defending A ristotelianism . Some Roman Catholic w riters, however, have accused Galileo w hile defending, or at least refraining from discussing, the scientific position of the Church.

A. C. Crombie’s position m ay serve as an instance: it is apologetic, eclectic, and up-to-date. If I understand Crombie rightly, he produces three argum ents against Galileo. First, Galileo was m istaken in having claimed th a t Copernicanism had been dem onstrated, since th e dem onstra­ tion of Copernicanism was produced only in the early nineteenth cen­ tu ry , w ith the discovery of stellar p arallax [323]. Secondly, as Einstein has shown, the tru th is th a t th ere is no immobile centre of th e world; the physicist’s choice of a centre is arb itra ry [327-8]. Thirdly, science concerns itself not w ith the search for tru th b ut w ith the proposal of w orking hypotheses w hich save the phenom ena [324-5, 328]. (Firstly, I did not borrow the bowl from you; secondly, I already retu rn ed it to you; and thirdly, it was cracked w hen I got it.) These argum ents have little reference to the historical situation; even w ere th ey correct they should be dismissed as m ere hindsights.

K oestler’s attack on Galileo the scientist includes Crombie’s main ammunition, and, in addition, th e view th a t Galileo was lying w hen he claimed th a t Copernicanism had been dem onstrated. This view I consider to be false, b ut not outrageous, and at least historical ra th e r than ana­ chronistic. Those who are infuriated by it are, I suppose, adherents of the principle th a t men of science are invariably honorable men, and

vice versa. This principle is very w idely accepted, as I have tried to

show elsewhere. Even Koestler, who explicitly rejects it, abides by it throughout his work, to the point of acknowledging Galileo as a great scientist only afte r the Inquisition broke his pride in 1633. This terrible opinion obviously clashes w ith ample evidence. Since K oestler usually endorses K epler’s judgm ent as sane, m oderate, and hum an, I shall metion only K epler’s view of Galileo. In his comments on Galileo’s As-

(5)

was a pow erful th in ker [355], b u t fa r from being an easy and pleasant character. K epler him self claims there [341-2] th at Galileo made state­ m ents he did not intend to make, m erely in the heat of the debate. Of course, K oestler’s view th a t Galileo’s statem ents to the Inquisition w ere lies goes much fu rth er; and, unlike K ep ler’s is nourished not by scientific considerations b u t by the Catholic hostile literature. But this is no reason to dismiss K oestler’s view as false, though ultim ately it has to be rejected—for other and b etter reasons.

K oestler’s attack on Galileo the scientist is nourished not only by the hostile Catholic attitude, bu t also by th e clumsily apologetic atti­ tude of others. To take one example, in his introduction to his selection from Galileo’s Assayer [226] D rake speaks of him as the teacher of experim ental philosophy (a phrase which Galileo never used). On the nex t page, he brushes aside the fact th a t Galileo’s Assayer concerns the defence of a false hypothesis, according to which comets consist of (earthly) vapors, adopted in order to rescue his own version of Coper- nicanism. D rake claims th a t this is quite irrelev an t to “the main point of the book, w hich lies not in th e hypothesis itself bu t in its use”. S antillana comes to Galileo’s rescue in another w ay [153]. It was right, as I understand Santillana, to dismiss the comets until it was possible to use them as dem onstrations of Copernicanism; and this only Newton could do. Obviously, this is both apologetic and untrue. K oestler’s con­ dem nation of Galileo the scientist on the ground th a t he did not plot the elliptic courses of comets is fain tly amusing, until one compares it w ith the clumsy apologies th a t Galileo’s defenders p ut forw ard to explain his failure to endorse the ellipse. G enerally, every time Galileo’s de­ fenders are apologetic, K oestler stresses the point which causes them discomfort; and every tim e the Catholic apologists show a weak point in Galileo’s scientific views K oestler follows them. And he regularly attrib utes some unpleasant m otives to Galileo. B ut let us leave the scientific side of the story for now.

The chief Catholic technique used on the political side of the story is th a t of pooh-poohing one decum ent and stressing another; and K oestler follows suit. Let us see how the political evidence is handled by Jam es Brodrick, the biographer of Cardinal Bellarm ine (1928). Santillana, no ally to him, refers to him as to “no less a historian than F ath er J. Brodick, S. J .”, attributing to him “discrim inating scholarship” and “Christian w arm th ” . Brodrick puts the whole blam e for the Church’s denunciation of Copernicanism in 1616 on Galileo. This thesis, looking ra th e r shaky, m ust needs be heavily supported by evidence. Brodrick quotes—from a letter w ritten by the then (1616) Tuscan am bassador to Rome—some unpleasant words about Galileo’s behavior in Rome and about the im prudence of a (young) Cardinal whom Galileo presum ably had sent to talk to the Pope about Copernicanism. Copernicanism was denounced, Brodrick tells

(6)

us, as the result of Galileo’s pressure, w hich the Tuscan am bassador was describing. Brodrick adds a footnote protesting against Galileo’s defenders (of before 1928): “insinuating th a t the am bassador was a bit of a fool”, and ignoring th e alleged fact th at he was a personal friend of Galileo, they dismiss or ignore his evidence.

On the same page w here he launches this complaint, Brodrick him ­ self suppresses a p a rt of the same letter, w hich contradicts his own story. According to B rodrick’s story, once Galileo extended enough pressure to get the m achine going, it had to go on its own course ac­ cording to established rules of procedure: th e Congregation of the Holy Office had to consult experts about th e status of Copernicanism, and to endorse the experts’ judgm ent. Y et according to the same le tte r of the Tuscan ambassador, the question was decided not a t all by the Congregation, not by any consultation, and according to no rules of procedure: the obscurantist Pope and C ardinal Bellarm ine w ere de­ term ined to condemn Copernicanism by hook or by crook.

It is possible to defend B rodrick’s omission: the am bassador’s story may be questioned because of being chronologically inconsistent w ith the Vatican files. B ut this defence of Brodrick will show how much he distorts the views of Galileo’s defenders w hen he says th a t th ey had dismissed the am bassador’s evidence for no good reason. According to the Tuscan am bassador th e decision against Copernicanism w as taken by the Pope and Bellarm ine on March 2nd 1616, w hereas according to the Vatican records the Congregation had passed its verdict against Coperni­ canism on F ebruary 25th. The am bassador says th a t the Pope has told the young Cardinal who supported Galileo th a t “th e question was to be ref e rre d to the C ardinals of the Holy Office”, sometime a fte r the question had already been referred to these Cardinals, and decided upon by them. The Pope could n o t have suggested on M arch th e 2nd to the

young C ardinal “to persuade him [Galileo] to give up th a t opinion

[Copernicanism]” if on F eb ru ary 26th B ellarm ine had already forced Galileo to be silent.

S antillana seems to explain aw ay the am bassador’s derogatory re­ m arks on Galileo in two ways. First, he views the am bassador as “a cyn­

ical m an of the w orld” who had deserted his acquaintance Galileo.

Secondly, he thinks th a t the m isinform ation in his le tte r is a sign of h is having been deceived by a prearran g ed leak designed to p u t the blame on Galileo. S antillana has not made up his m ind as to w hether the am bassador was a m ere acquaintance and “a cynical man of the w orld”, or a naive friend who was taken in by misleading inside infor­ m ation w hich he could easily have refu ted by hearing from Galileo about B ellarm ine’s threats. (All dramatis personae w ere present in Ro­ me then.)

(7)

he could, and did, follow B rodrick’s position ra th e r closely, and, in addition, stress every piece of evidence concerning which the defenders of Galileo have tried to gloss over som ew hat m ore glibly then they ought to have done. This is precisely the reason for m y viewing his w ork as much more significant th an th a t of other critics of Galileo, like Crombie or Brodrick. Even if we reject all of his views, and I doubt that we can do this, we m ust adm it th a t he has posed quite a num ber of serious problem s for those of us who side more w ith Galileo than w ith Bellarm ine. In any case, it is to be hoped th a t we shall never be able to re tu rn to the old idealized picture of Galileo.

3. KOESTLER’S PEN-PORTRAIT OF GALILEO AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

K oestler describes Galileo as an extrem ely unplesant and arrogant p er­ son, whose interest in science was m uch less a motive for his actions than his “hypersensitivity to criticism, and his irrepressible urge to get involved in a controversy” [432, 470]. A lthough great men of science m ay be as negative personalities as K oestler’s Galileo, and although one cannot entirely refu te K oestler’s picture of the young Galileo (it can easily be shown to contain exaggerations), one can show th a t the older Galileo found his personal salvation in science: he learned to rise to the occasion of defending the cause of science, and thus vastly im ­ proved his personal character. (It seems th a t K oestler’s historical figures suffer from the same defect as his fictional figures: they never change their characters.)

According to the accepted view of the trial, the Pope and his advis­ ers used the trial for an attack on science in general; it was a piece of self-assertion by obscurantists. Catholic historians, too, tend to accept this view. B ut this view conflicts w ith the following w ell-know n facts. The new Pope, U rban VIII, had encouraged Galileo to w rite the Dialogue or a t least let Galileo come out of six audiences w ith him w ith the impression th a t such was the case (which is practically the same thing). And th e book won the im prim atur. K oestler argues th a t th e encourage­ m ent was given to the scientist Galileo and th a t the trial was of the conceited and quarrelsom e Galileo who took the opportunity and fought his own private b attle instead of fighting for th e cause of science; th at by bullying ignorant censors Galileo succeeded in getting the im prim a­

tu r for a book of a different character than the one he was expected to

w rite; th a t his bluff was called in a very short time, and he had to pay for his arrogance.

Assuming th a t th e existence of th e Inquisition and censorship are not exactly encouragem ents to the freedom of thought, and assuming th a t the Inquisition was not created for the sole purpose of intim idating

(8)

arrogant scientists, K oestler’s contention th a t Galileo’s character was the cause of the trial cannot be taken literally. It m ust be rein terp reted as an exaggeration of the following view. U nfavorable for science as the social and political situation was, it was not so bad to make it impossible for a m an of science to defend Copernicanism reasonably and get aw ay w ith it. I t m ight have been possible—and, for th e sake of science, highly advisable—to get aw ay w ith a defence of Copernicanism by m aking a v erbal concession so as to allow opponents to save face. Given the atrocious illiberalism of the times, the C hurch’s behaviour was reason­ able in view of Galileo’s violent outbursts, extravangant claims, stu b ­ born unw illingness to compromise, and immense capacity to annoy and irritate practically anybody. Thus, private affairs upset public m at­ ters and led to the divorce between F aith and Science.

I t is this reinterpretation of K oestler’s presentation w hich w ill be exam ined here. We shall take th e hypothesis, exam ine w hat it can explain, w hat facts m ay conflict w ith it, and how it can be replaced by a b etter one. The hypothesis is, th a t Galileo was clever, vain, and hypersensitive. It follows, first, th a t he quarrelled obsessively, and second, th a t knowing his own weakness, he cleverly avoided quarrel as much as his vanity perm itted. It follows, fu rth er, th a t he was a ra th e r unpleasant person; not as friendless as K oestler makes him to be, b ut not too popular either. The historical facts the hypothesis explains are rath e r numerous. The hypothesis explains all the unpleasant details of Galileo’s early career; in p articu lar why, u ntil 1613, w hen he was almost fifty years old, Galileo never com mitted him self publicly to Copernicanism: as we concluded from th e hypothesis, he tried to avoid controversy w henever his v an ity perm itted. A fter he had declared his allegiance to Copernicanism, in 1613, he had, as we have concluded, to qu arrel obsessively, even if the result was th a t he destroyed himself. The problem remains: w hy did he sta rt defending Copernicanism? The answ er m ust be, his van ity prevented him from concealing his views any longer. How? H aving m ade some astronom ical discoveries, Galileo could not b u t stress, not to say exaggerate, their significance (because of his vanity). In other words, he could not avoid th e tem ptation of viewing his discoveries as dem onstrations of the tru th of Copernicanism.

This p a rt of K oestler’s story is logically neat. The evidence w hich he m arshals in its favor is h ardly new, but he has shown how glibly this evidence has been glossed over; y et he exaggerates its value, and makes it go a long way. Almost all his significant evidence relates to the period up to 1613. Up till then Galileo picked only quarrels which he could w in and w hich did not endanger his career. His com m itm ents to Copernicanism w ere vague enough not to cause him any serious trouble; he had a qu arrel w ith some m inor Dominicans about it, but he

(9)

was confident th a t he could win; and he did win. B ut there is evidence (see below) w hich contradicts the hypothesis: it is a fact th a t in 1613 he was psychologically quite capable of ignoring a challenge. Thus Koes- tle r’s story up to 1612, though highly exaggerated in its psychology, and very incorrect in disregarding Galileo’s early and passionate interest in tru th , is nonetheless largely correct in describing him as an unpleas­ ant, career-seeking, and ra th e r touchy, quarrelsom e fellow. In 1614 we find Galileo engaged in a battle w ith the m ighty Bellarmine, in which he does endanger his career and even his life. Since Galileo was not as hypersensitive as K oestler makes him out to have been, he must have had some reason for suddenly becoming so reckless. Let us, then, consider the following midification. Galileo had been career-m inded until about the age of fifty. But then he achieved great fame, and learned th a t tru th was much more im portant to him than fame. Many people seek fam e w hile neglecting to fight for the tru th , deceiving themselves all the time th a t th eir motive is respectable: once they have achieved fame, they say, th ey will be able and w illing to fig h t effectively for the cause of tru th . It is quite possible th a t Galileo held the same atti­ tude and carried out his plan sincerely. And w hen he started his fight he soon found out th a t fam e is of no im portance one w ay or another. Career-seekers norm ally deceive them selves in thinking th a t when they have achieved position and fame they w ill use it in their fight for the cause of tru th . Y et occassionally they are sincere. Assuming th at Galileo w as one of them , one has to adm it th a t he was also sincere. It m ust always be rem em bered th a t he was an unusual person; possibly he looked all th e tim e for a chance of getting his ideas across w ithout a battle; in any case, we know th a t he fought, and rose to the occasion w onderfully.

4. THE FALL OF GALILEO

Galileo’s visit to Rome in 1611, after publishing his Starry Message (1610), was a great success. It was a very dram atic change from his previous status. J u st before his journey to Rome he had been criticized ra th e r sharply, and his astronom ical discoveries had been declared chi­ merical. Only K epler had defended them, and upon faith, not after exam ination of the evidence. K epler had been w orried by the fact th a t all the evidence he had h eard was opposed to Galileo’s evidence, and had asked Galileo to nam e witnesses confirming his evidence. Galileo could not nam e any witness, very much to his fru stratio n and chagrin; and only w ith effort—so his le tter to K epler reads—could he tu rn his immense bitterness against his colleagues into scorn at the m ultitude, th eir stupidity, and their ignorance.

(10)

m ers of the Roman College endorsed most of his observations, and he found quite a few friends among them. He was cordially received even by Cardinal Bellarm ine, who had been Professor of Philosophy, M aster of Controversies, Rector of the Roman College, and rem ained one of the most pow erful figures in Rome until his death. B ellarm ine’s recog­ nition of Galileo was no sm all m atter, especially considering th a t Bel­ larm ine w as a staunch auth o ritarian and traditionalist, and had been one of the judges of Giordano Bruno, who had been b u rn t on th e stake b u t one decade before, w hereas Galileo was a follower of Bruno (see below), or at least suspected of being the follower of Bruno, as even K oestler cryptically admits. (K oestler’s dismissal of the thesis th a t Bruno was a m a rty r of science is unw orthy of criticism.)

Of course Galileo found opposition, too, which is not surprising. But in his case one m ight have expected all opposition to have become w eak­ er and w eaker w ith the passage of time. Yet Galileo’s position w ors­ ened—and very quickly too. In 1611 B ellarm ine shows his esteem of Galileo; in the middle of 1612 B ellarm ine w rites to Galileo, expressing his affection, respect, and readiness to be of any service (the function of this most unusual le tter has not been studied as yet). And then comes a change: in 1613 B ellarm ine speaks against Galileo in a private con­ versation w ith a priest who is a friend of Galileo, quoting Psalm 19 which describes the motion of the sun; the point is discussed in Gali­ leo’s Letter to Castelli of December 1613, and in at least one of B ellar­ m ine’s sermons [Brodrick, 335], preached soon afterw ards. (Like most of Galileo’s early works, this one was unpublished and p riv ately cir­ culated; B ellarm ine’s sermon was published early in 1615, but, very likely, it w as also privately circulated in 1614.) All is still w ithin the bounds of civility; th e rest of th e story is not. In A pril 1615 Bellarm ine creates a new nuance by launching a w arnings, suggesting th a t Galileo’s opinion is opposed to a decision of the Council of T rent (this is no small threat), and contradicts King Solomon (Ecclesiastes, “and the earth for ever stan d eth”), the wisest of all men; in about November or early Decem ber 1615 he expresses displeasure a t Galileo’s plan to come to Rome. This is reported by the Tuscan am bassador on December 5th, 1615, bu t Galileo is in such a h u rry to leave Florence th a t he never receives the am bassador’s w arning—he is in Rome on the 7th of De­ cember. (Koestler’s rep o rt is inaccurate; almost every one of his inaccu­ racies can be traced back to a lack of clarity of S antillana or Drake.) The situation is so baffling th a t until G ebler’s w ork of a century ago it was assumed th a t Galileo was summoned to Rome. As G ebler shows [71 f], he came to Rome voluntarily. G ebler explains this disastrous move as the result of Galileo’s unaw areness of the strength of his opponents’ dogmatism. This explanation is a bit naive, yet S antillana accepts it as he has no b etter one to offer.

(11)

Two months after Galileo’s arriv al in Rome nothing seems to have happened; then the pace guickens considerably. On F eb ru ary 18th, 1616 (or a little earlier), Galileo goes to the Holy Office [Santillana, 114—5]; on th a t day the Congregation assembles and on the n ex t day asks for ex pert opinion; though the problem is most difficult, the expert opinion against Copernicanism is procured w ithin a week; the Congregation is assembled .again on th e 25th; on the same day the decision is reached

and ratified and Bellarm ine is instructed to act; he acts on the 26th,

summoning Galileo to his palace and telling him to be silent or else. This chronology is based chiefly on the Vatican files. It is contra­ dicted, we rem em ber, by the Tuscan am bassador’s le tter of March 4th.

F ar be it from me to prefer the (possibly doctored) Vatican files to the am bassador’s (second hand) inform ation or vice versa. It is possible th a t the am bassador’s letter had been w ritten two weeks before it was dated, to be first delayed and then sent in a h u rry ; and other explana­ tions are possible. But, obviously, th ere was a great rush and tum ult. Why? Why?

The decision condemning Copernicanism, which was taken on February 25th, 1616, was not published until years later, and perhaps it was not intended for publication at all. It was acted upon, at least according to the Vatican files. The Vatican files report the decision of F ebruary 25th and B ellarm ine’s w arning to Galileo on F ebruary 26th. The public, ho­ wever, knew only of a decree, published on March 5th, which condem ­ ned Copernicanism in a surprisingly mild tone, and of a certificate of honor given to Galileo by Bellarm ine on 26th May, which contradicts the main docum ent in the Vatican files. Wohlwill, Gebler, and Santil­ lana, have all argued more than convincingly th a t Bellarm ine’s inside report and his certificate of honour to Galileo are significantly differ­

ent. Both these documents, however, indicate how seriously Galileo was taken by the C hurch authorities. Why? How could he throw the Church leaders into a panic and m ake them act in such a h u rry and in so confused a manner? W here lay the power of th a t isolated sick man?

There are other points which may be explained by the assumption th a t some confusion resulted from the hasty proceedings of the Church authorities, and th at some of the steps which w ere taken in a h u rry were later regretted. Santillana argues th a t the wording of the condemnation of Copernicanism is confused to the point of meaninglessness [139]. Moreover, th ere is a discrepancy between two Vatican reports about B ellarm ine’s w arning to Galileo, and between each of them and the certificate of honor w hich Bellarm ine gave Galileo. Since the discovery of the relevant Vatican documents in 1867, the trial of Galileo of 1633 has often been alleged to be legally connected w ith Bellarm ine’s w arning of 1616, and consequently much ink has been spilt on the w orthless

(12)

legalistic issue, which of the three docum ents concerning the w arning is the correct one. The more interesting question, I suggest, is w hy w ere the C hurch authorities in such a hurry?

K oestler’s explanation of the tu rn of events rests on a subtle error: he uses the im plausibility of his own explanation of th e C hurch’s con­ dem nation of Copernicanism to explain the C hurch’s (alleged) subsequent attem p t to forget this condemnation. This is the same kind of offence as th a t com mitted by a contractor who bills you both for a shoddy job and for the inspection and repairs of its defects. Galileo’s bad tem per and ability to annoy people, says Koestler, caused the move. These, obviously, could not move even a Pope, let alone a V atican office, to a rash condemnation of an im portant doctrine. Therefore, says Koestler, the condem nation was soon buried.

S antillana’s story is exactly the opposite. The Church was going to condemn Copernicanism—we are not exactly told w hy—and all th a t Galileo w anted was to prevent a rash action. Santillana him self adm its in a w ay th a t Galileo was the person who had started the affair. Galileo w rote to K epler in 1597, telling him th a t he had new proofs for Coper­ nicanism (his law of inertia, I suppose) but would not publish; K epler urged him, in reply, to publish—in G erm any if Italy was too intolerant; Galileo rem ained p rudent enough to say nothing until 1610. “Now [1610] th a t certainty [of the Copernican doctrine] has been reached”, says Santillana, “the motives for silence th a t he had explained to K epler no longer w ere valid” [14]. All th a t K oestler has to do in order to criticize Santillana is to explain to his reader th ree points: first, w hat w ere the motives for silence (K oestler’s answ er being, Galileo’s fear of criticism and ridicule); second, w hat was the certainty (that A ristot­ le was wrong, not th a t Copernicus was right); and third, w hat was Galileo’s campaign (not to “build up a tidal wave of opinion” [15], since the wave was building up too rapidly anyhow, but, says Koestler, to force his opponents into public admission of th eir errors and into public acceptance of the new and as y et unproven doctrine).

Santillana does not explain cogently w hy Galileo started his un­ fortunate campaign. He argues, w ith the aid of documents [135], th a t the softening of the blow to Galileo in 1616 resulted from the strength of Galileo’s (theological) Letter to the Grand Duchess w ritten shortly beforehand. Yet, clearly, this letter, and its earlier version, the L etter

to Castelli, had provided Galileo’s enemies w ith the grounds for attack,

and had made Bellarm ine an enemy. W hen he describes how Galileo started the campaign, Santillana entirely ignores the Tuscan am bassa­ dor’s letter of December 5, 1615, in which he is very opposed to the campaign; b u t w hen discussing its failure, he agrees w ith the am bassa­ dor [117] th a t in December 1615 Rome was “no place to come and argue about the Moon”. This is te rrib ly apologetic. It is v ery h ard to

(13)

piece S antillana’s exciting story into a simple p attern of explanation. W hen it emerges, it seems incredible: though Galileo started a cam­ paign, his opponents are blam ed for having started a counter-campaign. P erhaps the methods of Galileo and all his allies w ere more honest than those of all his opponents (this has not been shown); in any case, Galileo was endangering his opponents’ faith, their social and political positions, and even their personal security. S antillana’s siding fully w ith Galileo and against his opponents is a bit h ard to endorse.

S antillana’s uneasy feelings seem to show clearly, for instance [53], w hen he explains th a t Galileo’s L etter to Castelli was w ritten in reply to Bellarm ine’s views as expressed in a private discussion w ith a priest who was a friend of Galileo. As Galileo did not accept all challenges, this is an unsatisfactory explanation. Moreover, it is incredible luck for Galileo th a t of all anti-Copernican passages in the Scriptures Bellarm ine should quote in th a t private discussion Psalm 19, knowingly giving Galileo a chance to expound his neo-Platonist light-m etaphysics (as Santillana him self notices [154], especially since Bellarm ine thought he had much stronger biblical am m unition, viewing King Solomon

(Ecclesiastes) much greater an astronomical authority than King David (Psalms). This, like other facts, is explicable by assuming th a t it was

Galileo who provoked Bellarm ine to discuss Psalm 19: the person in position is seldom th e m ore provocative p arty w hen he bears no malice and is not looking for more troubles than he already has; especially w hen he has plenty. (Using Psalm 19 Galileo was em ulating Pico’s Oratio).

If we view Galileo as selfish and successful, we cannot explain his campaign and defeat in 1616. K oestler’s psychological theory about his obsessiveness, in particular, is refuted by the evidence. If, however, we view Galileo as devoted to science, we cannot explain w hy he did not fight for Copernicanism in 1611, unless we assume th a t he shrew dly postponed the battle to a more propitious moment; which makes his battle in 1616 an incredible folly [Gebler, 70-75]. There are two trad i­ tions about the case, the hostile, best represend by (Brodrick and) Koestler, and the apologetic, best represented by (Gebler and) S antil­ lana. The easiest w ay to refu te these two traditions is to see how the w riters who belong to them struggle w ith the events leading to, and including, the condemnation of Copernicanism of 1616.

5. THE CHANGE IN GALILEO’S BEHAVIOUR

K oestler’s story of Galileo’s prudence and selfishness up to about 1612, is hard to ignore altogether. A dm ittedly, Koestler is m istaken in claim ­ ing th at the Starry Message of 1610 contains no “statem ent in favour of the Copernican system ” [430, 431] (the mistake may have resulted

(14)

from reading D rake [85]). Adm ittedly, K oestler is m istaken in suggesting th a t the com m itm ent to Copernicanism in the L etters on the Sunspots of 1613 is “somewhat vague in form ”. (In the th ird L etter on the S u n ­

spots Galileo says, “An understanding of w hat Copernicus w rote in his Revolutions suffices for the most exp ert astronom ers ... to verify ... his

system” [Drake, 130].) These commitments, nevertheless, are not as clear and bold as his p riv ate com mitments; and th e absence of a suffi­ ciently clear commitment involved another failing, nam ely inability to m ake proper acknowledgement to ones who w ere clearly committed. A courtier who had lunch w ith K epler tells Galileo (15 A pril 1610) about the conversation they had: “He said concerning your book [Starry

Message] th a t tru ly it has revealed the divinity of your talent, bu t th a t

you' hajvei given cause of com plaint ... since you m ake no m ention of those w riters who gave the signal and the occasion for your discovery, nam ing among them Giordano Bruno ..., Copernicus, and him self” [Sin­ ger, 189]. In order to explain this unacknowledged indebtedness, one has to discuss Galileo’s methodology, w hich is cryptic, and the w ay he made his famous discoveries, w hich everyone praises b ut no one dis­ cusses.

B runo’s methodology is perhaps a proper starting-point. In the be­ ginning of his first dialogue in his On the Infin ite (and in the beginning of th e last dialogue in the same book) Bruno makes it clear th a t he is an apriorist, who, however, does not regard observation as useless; the use of the testim ony of the senses is “solely to stim ulate our reason, to accuse, to indicate, testify in p art; not to testify completely, still less to judge or to condemn.” This passage seems to me to be of crucial im portance. I do not think th a t Galileo kept to B runo’s methodology all his life, or th a t he was clear about his own view of the m atter. In his

Dialogue on the Tw o System s (1632), w hen Simpicio asks Salviati (i. e.

Galileo) w hether he is an apriorist or not, Salviati refuses to answ er and even bamboozles his audience [Santillana’s edition, 202-3, and S antillana’s note there; cf. Wiener, passim]. B ut at least in his early period, and up to his Assayer (1623), his following of Bruno is quite conspicuous, and even in his Dialogues, and in his method of w riting scientific dialogues, he is a Brunist.

The reason for Galileo’s strong adherence to Bruno m ay be found in his early, mechanical works, On M otion (1590), and On Mechanics (1600), which w ere published only centuries later. Galileo started by ac­ cepting A ristotle’s mechanics, continued by accepting Archimedes and slowly used his own Archimedeanism and clear thinking to expel his own A ristotelianism step by step. A few bits of early d rafts of On Motion are published in the English edition, which show how slow was his progress. Nor was the process finished by 1600. Tow ards the end of On Mechanics Galileo develops his own law of inertia in order to explain Archim edes’

(15)

screw, yet soon afterw ards, when trying to explain w hat happens when a ham m er hits a nail on its head, he employs an A ristotelian theory of im petus rath e r than his own Archimedean theory. As Lane Cooper has suggested [48 and note], Galileo’s early mechanical works should be viewed as p a rt and parcel of a Renaissance attem pt to reconstruct both A r­ chimedes’ philosophy and certain ancient criticism s of Aristotle. The effort involved was much greater than one m ay imagine: Archimede- anism was revived before A ristotelianism was throw n out, and the con­ tra s t between the two was discovered by a long and arduous process. Since his investigations w ere prim arily conceived as logical problems [Fahie, 19; Koyre, b) Conclusion; Cooper, 48], not as empirical ones, Galileo could h ardly be interested in experim ents, and this is w hy he was so interested in methodology and laid such an em phasis on clarity. (Galileo, and to a lesser extent even Bruno, was a forerunner of Descartes in viewing clarity and distinctness—b ut also sim plicity—as criteria of truth).

An impressive example, w hich Galileo discusses in meticulous detail in the Dialogue as well as in earlier works, is this. Everybody (including Leonardo, incidentally) had taken it for granted th a t a smooth surface reflects light more strongly than a rough one. Consequently, a man on the moon should see the oceans on earth as b righter than the continents. Only clear thinking, says Galileo, can show this to be an error; no am ount of experience w ith w alls and m irrors has helped to eradicate it. And a corollary from this correction is most im portant since it confirms Co- pernicanism by showing th a t the moon, being bright, is a rough surface like the earth, not a crystalline body made of the pure fifth essence. Hence we may expect confirm ations of Copernicanism to come more easily from clarity th an from experience.

W ith this in mind we can easily understand K epler’s complaint. Ga­ lileo’s Starry Message contains discoveries which confirm Copernicanism: th e m ountains on the moon and the moons of Ju piter. To this one should add the alleged moons of S aturn and the phases of Venus, which fall in the same category. In all of these cases, there is no doubt, anticipation of the discoveries was essential to making them. As we have seen, Galileo knew, by reasoning alone, th a t the moon has a rough surface. In his

Starry Message he describes how he looked for hours w ith a telescope at

a dark spot on the edge of the light p art of the moon, until it disappeared, as the shadow on an earthly valley disappears at sunrise. He could not have made such an observation w ithout an anticipation, w ithout, p ar­ ticularly, following K epler’s idea of imagining him self standing on Mars and gazing at Earth. It is h ard to exaggerate the significance and novelty of this idea [Einstein, a) 24-5, b) 225]. K epler’s indebtedness to Coperni­ cus for it is obvious; w hen Galileo imagines him self standing in a lunar valley w aiting for sunrise, then, he is indebted to K epler and Copernicus

(16)

at once. Because he was inspired by Copernicus’ theory, Galileo took his discoveries to be empirical dem onstration of it (like Bruno he did not think th at em pirical dem onstration is complete). That the same holds for the moons of Ju p ite r and Saturn, as well as for the phases of Venus, and th a t here Galileo is in debt to B runo’s speculations about the infinity of suns and satellites, is too clear to dem and any fu rth e r elaboration.

Now all this is largely a reconstruction. Galileo him self said little about methodology until afte r he w rote his L etter on the Sunspots (1613), probably because he was still very prudent. K oestler does not quote Ga­ lileo’s style in this work. Could this be because it is unusually civil, p artly even submissive, alm ost up to the very end? Also the L etter on the S u n ­

spots is interesting because it shows th a t Galileo’s earlier Discourse on Floating Bodies (1612) had not been intended to arouse opposition, and

th a t w hen it did arouse opposition Galileo took it lightly, and decided not to answ er his opponents, considering him self successful enough in converting judicious people [Drake, 128-9]. This passage K oestler does not quote; rather, to prove his thesis about Galileo’s “irrepressible urge to get involved in a controversy” he claims, in his urge2 to condemn

2 It is worth quoting Koestler in full on this point, to allow the reader to notice his following three striking errors, (i) Koestler himself, though he has published some interesting thoughts about Archimedes, completely fails to restate the contrast between Archimedes and Aristotle, (ii) Yet he views Galileo’s opponents as unworthy of being criticized, (in) He can be unbelievably unfair to Galileo, to the point of viewing even his (alleged) anticipation of criticism — the thing which every good author does — as a vice. “After his return, in the summer of 1611, from his Roman triumph to Florence, Galileo become immediately involved in several disputes. He had published a treatise on “Things that Float on Water” — a title that sounds harmless enough. But in this pioneer work on modern hydro­ statics Galileo had embraced Archimedes’ view that bodies float or sink according to their specific gravity, against the Aristotelian view that this depends on their shape. The backwoodsmen were out at once in full cry, swinging their stone axes. They were the more irate as Galileo, instead of letting the facts speak for them­ selves, had employed his favorite trick of anticipating the peripatetics’ arguments, building them up in a mockserious manner, and then demolishing them with glee” [428]. The absurdity of Koestler’s condemnation, however, is no excuse for the absurdity of Drake’s praise; on the contrary, Koestler’s indebtedness shows how easy it is to change the nuance in a passage from absurd praise into its opposite, while leaving the key points untouched. “Shortly after Galileo’s return to Florence in the summer of 1611 he found himself once more in collision with the followers of Aristotle... Now they were confronted with a record of experimental data that anyone could verify at will, and the only thing open to question was the matter of interpretation. But in this they were no match for Galileo, whose specialty was the study of experimental results; and even in their own field of constructing ingenious arguments they were hopelessly outclassed for once. Galileo had in fact all their arguments, strengthening these, adding others that had not occurred to them, and then demolishing the whole structure with his own demonstrations and proofs. It was a device which he was to employ extensively in his later works, and one which accounts for his vast influence with nonprofessional readers as well as his extreme unpopularity with the targets of his polemic compositions” [79-80]. This praise is reminiscent of the tragedy of Nijinsky who was hurt by public enthusiasm for his jumps; he wanted to be appreciated as a dancer and not as an acrobat. Drake admires Galileo as an acrobat-polemicist rather than as a teacher of critical thinking. Incidentally, what Drake and Koestler say about Galileo’s new experimental facts, about the ease with which Galileo demolished his opponents, etc., are sheer fantasy [c/. Fahie, 143-5], as the following paragraphs show.

(17)

Galileo, th a t Galileo raised opposition in w riting his Discourse on Floa­

ting Bodies quite unnecessarily.

A philosopher called Buonamici, who was probably Galileo’s teacher in the university of Pisa, discovered (what Galileo did not know w hen drafting his On Motion) th a t A rchim edes’ hydrostatic theory belongs to the Platonic tradition of explaining levity (or buoyancy) as caused by the gravity of the medium, and is inconsistent w ith the A ristotelian tradition of assuming both gravity and levity as essential causes of motion. Con­ sequently Buonamici rejected A rchim edes’ view. The chief objection to A ristotle’s view is th a t boats m ade of m etal float. This, A ristotle explain­ ed aw ay (at the very end of De Caelo) by an auxiliary hypothesis about the resistance of w ater (surface tension), as exem plified by floating me­ tallic needles and thin boards. Archimedes probably refuted this auxiliary hypothesis about floating m etal boats. His own treatise On Floating Bo­

dies explains w hy m etal boats float, and w ithout any auxiliary hypo­

thesis; b ut it contains no criticism of any other doctrine. Galileo took up Buonamici’s critical mode of thinking; and “speaking always w ithout di­ m inution of his [Buonamici’s] singular learning” [22] he refuted his views by reconstructing A rchim edes’ criticism of Aristotle. The objection to A rchim edes’ view, however, is the fact th a t m etallic needles and boards do float. Galileo tried to answ er this objection. This he failed to do (since the objection is unanswerable). He w riggled out of the difficulties by sheer ability to confuse a simple issue. Following Archimedes, Galileo claimed th a t the m etal needle or board m ust behave like a m etal boat and expel w ater of a weight slightly exceeding its own. Following Aris­ totle, Galileo’s adversaries denied this. This was the crux of the argu­ m ent concerning Galileo’s views, and he was plainly m istaken. He ad­ duced beautiful em pirical refutations of A ristotle; and he was simply con­ vinced th a t Archimedes’ geometrical dem onstrations w ere perfect.

B ut of course, m istaken as Galileo was concerning his own views, his criticism of Buonamici and his followers is valid. Regrettably, he was careful not to use all the am m unition which was at his disposal, judging by his earlier (unpublished) works. The first half of the Discourse on

Floating Bodies is a discussion of the criticism s and rejoinders of both

sides. The rest of the volume is a reconstruction of a P latonist rejoinder to A ristotle’s criticism of the theory th a t the levity of a body is caused by the gravity of the medium. This goes beyond Buonamici and his fol­ lowers; it is extrem ely interesting. Even D rake has to adm it [XI-XII] th a t the only novelty in this book is Galileo’s (reconstruction of A rchi­ medes’) criticism of Aristotle. In this Galileo was continuing the job which Buonamici started. However, his superiority to Buonamici here was a source of trouble. Buonamici was not enough of a clear and critical think er to have abandoned A ristotle’s views. And in backing Aristotle, who was the accepted rig h t horse, he was allowed by the public to use

(18)

logic alone. As Galileo was backing Archimedes, the socially unaccepted horse, the public forced him (by appeals to his employer, etc.) to produce not logic b ut experim ental facts. This pressure he m ay have anticipated, and this anticipation, plus his prudence, m ay explain w hy he was silent for years. A fterw ards, w hen he had become famous, he published only a small p art of his criticism of A ristotle, and w hile speaking of him w ith great civility, saying (untruthfully, I think) “he hath exquisitely philos­ ophiz’d ” [64]. B ut the small dose of criticism was enought to arouse dan­ gerous opposition, of the kind which D rake and K oestler ignore, b ut which can be judged from the following event. F ath e r G rienberger, a Jesuit astronom er of the Roman College, to whom Galileo referred in 1615 as to “th a t excellent m athem atician and my very dear friend and p atro n ”, w rote in 1614 “to a close friend of Galileo to say th a t w ere it not for the deference which by the direction of his superios he was obliged to show tow ards A ristotle, he would have spoken his m ind clearly on the m atter, in which Galileo was perfectly rig h t” [Brodrick, 347; Santillana, 118n; surprisingly, neither gives any reference]. (Incidentally, F ather G rien­ berger seems to have rem ained a friend to the last; but he could hardly be of any help to Galileo, it seems, because of his vows of obedience.)

The im portance of the early (1612 and before) mechanical w orks of Galileo lies in his realization of the im portance of logic; his considering criticism and clarity to be essential for scientific discourse. Q uarrelsom e as he could be, he confined his great discoveries prior to 1610 to a small inner circle, because, like most quarrelsom e people, he knew w ith whom not to quarrel. B ut then, in 1610 fame had been achieved, and he found th a t ideas m attered to him more than w ordly position. He sends a feeble feeler in the form of On Floating Bodies in 1612, and soon finds a w all of silence. From now on he becomes reckless and decides to take the bull by its (theological) horns not w ithstanding any risk to his own position. K oestler’s pru den t Galileo ceased to exist in 1614-5, and the reckless Ga­ lileo had an entirely different character from the one which K oestler ascribes to him. In short, the young Galileo was quarrelsom e b ut p ru ­ dent; the Galileo who got into trouble w ith the Church was a changed man.

6. GALILEO’S FAITH AND FATE

I t is hard to imagine how much of science was a mere dream a t first. That much of it was (pseudo) Pythagerean light-mysticism, has slowly transpired through works of E. A. B u rtt and others. That Pythagoreanism was deeply linked then w ith Cabbalism and alchem y has been shown by a few scholars, such as Blau, Gombrich, and Miss Yates. How much

(19)

of the methodology of the time was a m ystical dream is a story which has not yet been to ld .3

In Galileo’s days, hypotheses—say P tolem y’s—w ere claimed to en­ compass all known relevant phenomena, but not to describe any reality; also, usually they w ere over-complicated. These two points w ere connect­ ed: reality was always assumed to be simple, w hereas the appearances w ere known to be complicated; hence a complicated hypothesis could be posed only as a means of calculating em pirical results, not as a tru th about reality. Today the term for such a hypothesis is “a working hy­ pothesis”; traditionally, such a hypothesis was called “a m athem atical hypothesis” or “a m ere hypothesis” [Popper, 168]. One of the reasons for not suggesting hypotheses about reality was, no doubt, the idea that A ristotle had said everything about reality (though the relations between reality and appearances m ust then be adm itted to rem ain obscure). The other reason for giving up attem pts to describe reality, according to P opper’s suggestion, was the acceptance of P lato’s and A ristotle’s idea th at statem ents about reality m ust be dem onstrable (methodological essentialism), plus the realization th at dem onstrations w ere inaccessible [78ff, 151].

In an interesting preface to his Three Copernican Treatises Edward Rosen discusses Copernicus’ use of the word “hypothesis”. He argues th a t Copernicus (and K epler) denied th at Copernicus’ hypothesis was a m ere hypothesis or a m athem atical hypothesis—it was a dem onstrated hypothesis. Its being dem onstrated was the same as its not being m athe­ matical: there was no other known alternative. That it was dem onstrat­ ed was shown by its simplicity. Here comes K oestler’s very im portant point, which m ay have been known all along the way, but which (as S antillana’s and D rake’s fu ry illustrates) was never driven home so well:

3 Wolfson sees a continuity of method from Antiquity to date [a) 25; b) 106 ff], whereas Popper considers the Middle Ages as the outcome of the death of the Greek methods and the Renaissance of science as their revival [151]. The scholastic methods, so characteristic of the Middle Age , can be traced to the Talmud, Philo, early commentator’s on Aristotle, and Aristotle himself. The scholastic method is the critical method as employed elsewhere, in Antiquity or in modern science and scholarship, but with the proviso that the fundamental tenets remain unchallenged plus the technique of inventing ad-hoc hypotheses in order to protect them. The criticism of the fundamental tenets was offered by the mystic irrationalists who thus entrenched the identification of rationalism with Aristotelianism. Moreover, since the content of their criticism was identical with (and borrowed from) parts of the Aristotelian commentaries, what distinguished them was their method: by forbidding ad-hoc ripostes they turned innocuous flashes of debates into deadly hits. This may explain why the principle of simplicity was of such great methodol­ ogical import and mystical excitement at the same time (and violating it was so sinful). The peak of the mystic criticism is achieved by A1 Gazali and Crescas [Wolfson, a) llff], both of whom view their attack on Aristotle as an attack on rationalism. Crescas, however, being a Jew (and thus an adherent to the command­ ment to study the Law), finds a limited role for reason. The fact that criticism rises in the Renaissance together with mystic irrational cabbalism or Pythagoreanism or Neo-Platonism (e.g., Boccaccio, Pico, Cusanus) is thus no accident. [See also Yates, b) especially conclusion.]

(20)

hard as he tried, Copernicus failed to show th a t his simple hypothesis accounts for the known facts w ithout adding to it m any epicycles which render it very far from simple. This m ay explain his immense reluctance to publish: his idea of sim plicity was a dream; not m erely a program m e which he could only hope to accomplish but which he never did; it was the illusion th a t the program m e had been (nearly) accomplished. But criticism and clarity w ere integral p arts of the dream, and so the Coper- nicans had to criticize their own views even after they had claimed th a t these w ere the tru th s about reality, and hence dem onstrated, and hence clear and simple. The contradictions and non-sequiturs here should de­ light Koestler. That K epler had deceived him self in this fashion he tells us, but th a t Galileo could also deceive him self thus he denies. He scolds Galileo for consciously deceiving people w hen talking about the circular planetary orbits of the Copernican system, for not caring w heth­ er he was speaking the tru th in th a t instance, and for being obsessed w ith circles.

L et us allow the accused to speak [Drake, 262-3, D rake and O’Malley, 279]: “it is not I” says Galileo “who w an t the sky to have th e noblest [i. e. circular] shape because of its being the noblest body ... Never having read the pedigrees and patents of nobility of shapes, I do not know which of them are more and w hich of them are less noble, nor do I know th eir rank in perfection. I believe th a t in a w ay all shapes sire ancient an noble”—w hich is an explicit com m itm ent to P la to ’s doctrine of Ideas, from which Galileo shrinks at once to an almost posi­ tivist attitude: “or, to p ut it b etter [sic], th a t none of them are noble and perfect, or ignoble and imperfect, except in so fa r as for building walls a square shape is more perfect than the circular, and for wagon wheels the circle is more perfect than the triangle.” And y et in the same work (The Assayer, 1623), he claims [241 or 197] he would accept no path for a heavenly body save a regular one, such as a circle, a spiral, or an ellipse! Clearly quite a few exciting ideas interplay here, and Galileo him self is tossed between them. T hat he was aw are of Coper­ nicus’ epicycles, and w orried about them, is also clear from The As-

sdyer [264], w here he is very proud of having disposed of Copernicus’

socalled third motion of the earth. Like Copernicus and Kepler, he has both dem onstrated the hypothesis already, and is also going to complete the dem onstration p retty soon. For, obviously, dem onstration is the same as getting rid of all epicycles! This is not our idea of dem onstration, but it was his: Galileo both thinks th at the epicycles had been elim inated, and that he would be able to elim inate them p retty soon—more by intel­ lectual ingenuity than by observation. It is h ard to believe th a t the greatest logical mind of his age, and th e father of scientific method, could think thus; but we should rem em ber th a t such thinking occurs already in Copernicus’ and K epler’s various works, as well as in Galileo’s

(21)

own On Mechanics (of 1600), w hen he had no possible vested interest in his blunder. It m erely comes to illu strate Galileo’s own point of how difficult it is to avoid inconsistencies.

K oestler contrasts the ancient Phythagoreans w ith modern scientists: they lived blissfully before the split betw een F aith and Reason (which Galileo brought about), and the m odern scientists live in a w orld of strife, in a divided house of F aith and Reason. He views Pythagoreanism as a healthy m ixture of F aith and Reason. B ut he scolds Galileo for his m ed­ dling in theology! Not only did Galileo declare him self openly a member of the new Pythagorean m ovem ent—his faith in science itself was a kind of religion (and still is w ith most of us); the Inquisition referred to him as a Pythagorean, and Bellarmine viewed him as a religious reformer. And rightly so. And w ith th e zeal of reform ers he fought, and took risks. K oestler thinks th at the reform might have been im plem ented from w ithin (by the Jesu it astronom ers, chiefly), and th a t O utsider Galileo only spoiled m atters by iterfering and by annoying the Jesu it astronom ers until they became staunch anti-Copernicans. Yet K oestler has given not a single piece of evidence for the view th a t the Catholic Church has ever been reform ed w ithout a b itter struggle. And though we may easily understand, and need not resent, the official theologians’ resentm ent of Galileo’s theolog­ ical w ritings, it is rath e r hard to understand K oestler’s w ery sim ilar resentm ent of the same. The w ay he overlooks the fact th at his darling K epler was engaged in sim ilar theological exercises is a serious case of bias. Had Galileo’s theology been accepted by the Church directly from him, he m ight have become a saint, ra th e r than Bellarmine. There was a chance th a t this would happen, both in 1616, w hen Bellarmine got into a panic, and afte r the death of Bellarm ine and of th e Pope, w hen the new Pope, U rban VIII, encouraged Galileo to w rite his Dialogue. But even if he had no chance against Bellarmine, his sincerity and courage, as well as his im portant contribution to Catholic theology, ought to be appreciat­ ed (and m ay be appreciated in the future, even by Rome; rem em ber Joan of Arc!).

L et us glance for a m om ent at Galileo the Catholic reform er. In his

L etter to the Grand Duchess [Drake, 181] he offers his view for the

Church to consider, he presents it neither as the known tru th nor as a point of public debate. Y et the point is th a t we ought to separate theol­ ogy from astronom y so as to enable free critical discussion amongst astro­ nomers. A nd he comes dangerously closely to Brunos’ position, for which Bruno was burnt, and a t least he attacks (Bruno’s judge) Bellarm ine quite clearly along B runist lines: “I question the tru th of the statem ent th a t the Church commands us to hold as m atters of faith all physical conclusions bearing the stam p of harm onious [i.e. unanimous] interpretation by all the F athers of the Church. I think this m ay be an arb itrary simplification of various council decrees by certain people [Bellarmine] to favour their

(22)

own opinions” [203]. We m ay rem em ber th a t Bruno was willing to recant only after an argum ent w ith the Pope, not on the au th ority of his judges (amongst whom was Bellarmine). K oestler asserts th a t Bruno, a m eta­ physician ra th e r than a scientist, had nothing to do w ith Galileo’s case, and th a t w hen Galileo stood before the Inquisition in 1633 “he was afraid ”. Galileo’s words which I have quoted, w ritten fifteen years after Bruno was b u rn t on the stake, do not seem to be the w ords of a coward; one m ay fail to notice the sim ilarity betw een B runo’s and Galileo’s scientific views, b ut h ardly th eir religious views in general, and their submission to the Pope cum defiance of th e Inquisition in particular; one m ay dislike th eir submission to the Pope, b u t one m ust adm it th a t they w ere brave and sincere Catholics, even though the Cathdlic Church cannot as yet adm it this.

To conclude, Koestler expresses m ore than once his desire not to be wise after th e event, b u t he is wise after the event in Galileos’ case, at least. He applies hindsight w hen he applies w hat he (erroneously) thinks is th e p roper criterion for judging w hether Copernicanism had been de­ m onstrated, instead of looking for Galileo’s own criterion. And he applies hindsight w hen he takes it for granted th a t Galileo was bound to lose his theological campaign for Copernicanism. Galileo had a very good chance of winning it; b u t the point to stress is th a t we ought to investigate w h eth ­

er he had a good chance, and, w hat is m ore im portant, we ought to no­ tice th a t he thought he had a good chance to win the battle. (Indeed, at one point he thought the battle was already won [c/. Gebler, 177].) Trying to explain his behavior thu s m ay be more interesting th an viewing it as irrational, as K oestler does, by saying th a t he was obsessed w ith his need to quarrel regardless of the consequences. In brief, K oestler does not attem pt a rational reconstruction of th e b attle as it appeared before it was over.

7. THE DIALOGUE AND THE TRIAL OF GALILEO

The most difficult p art to reconstruct is the w ay in w hich a b attle can be fought from w ithin. If one rejects an im portant doctrine, one becomes an outsider; and if one does not reject it first, one does not wish to fight for its official rejection. Does not one’s attem p t to alter the official doctrine show one’s conviction th a t it is false? Indeed, it is universally assum ed th a t Galileo did not believe w h at he was told (by Bellarmine) to believe; defenders of Galileo, like S antillana [e.g., 151], view his pro­ fessions of faith as ironical, and Catholic apologists as hypocritical. Now (being an agnostic and a Jew ) I am a person poorly qualified to explain th e fact th a t Catholics are perm itted by th e ir C hurch sim ultaneously to believe in a doctrine and to criticize it; y et I wish to state categorically

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

ach in the laboratory of Feliks Nawrocki (1838–1902), Professor of Physiology at Imperial University Warsaw. After a tracheotomy, artificial respiration was applied and the animal

On the grounds of the above criteria – not sharp yet but already giving orientation – one may try to distinguish the concept of a dilemma from other practical problems. Thanks

We give characterization conditions for the inverse Weibull distribution and generalized extreme value distributions by moments of kth record values...

we define n-th root selections in fields of characteristic 6= 2, that is subgroups of the multiplicative group of a field whose existence is equivalent to the ex- istence of a

No precise date can be attributed to the invention of the thermometer, although it is probable that between the years 1593 and 1603 Galileo Galilei worked on an in- strument to

W konsekwencji utrzymywanie, że określona interpre- tacja życia i dzieła Galileusza nie jest poprawna, a nawet szkodliwa, bo dla przykładu uznająca go za człowieka wierzącego, jest

Kolon ten jest bardzo ciekawy, albo- wiem wymieniane w nim procedury (ograniczenia, rozróżnienia, prze- kręcanie słów i fajerwerki [słowne]) zdają się być ironiczną

Clearly the results of this note do not depend on the partic- ular choice ξ n = e 2πi/n of a primitive nth root