• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Responsible innovation of shale gas: Understanding the controversy

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Responsible innovation of shale gas: Understanding the controversy"

Copied!
5
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

1

Extended abstract

Responsible innovation of shale gas: understanding the controversy

To be presented at WICaNeM 2014 – Capri, 4-6 2014

Eefje Cuppen (presenter), Aad Correljé, Marloes Dignum, Udo Pesch and Behnam Taebi, Sanne Remmerswaal

Delft University of Technology, Faculty of Technology, Policy and Management

Introduction

The extraction of unconventional gas has engendered public controversies in many countries around the world. The controversy on shale gas is just one in a range of examples of energy projects that face difficulties in the implementation phase. The interaction between citizens, businesses, local authorities and environmental organizations may be, or become, problematic, and turn energy projects into difficult and risky enterprises. The government and the energy industry therefore consider the antagonists in such cases as showstoppers. Thus, policies and communication are organized accordingly and the value-laden basis of controversies is ignored. Hence national authorities and energy companies complain that either the public is ill-informed (Wynne, 2001), resistant to scientific information, or only concerned with its own short-term interests (Bell, Gray, & Haggett, 2005; Wolsink, 2006). This is referred to as the “technocratic pitfall” (Roeser, 2011).

In this paper we aim to clarify these controversies by focusing on the fundamental public values that underlie shale gas developments. This value-laden basis of social conflict is often ignored. We argue that the contestation finds it roots in the diversity of (conflicting) stakeholders’ values (Correljé, Cuppen, Dignum, Pesch, & Taebi, forthcoming). This means that responsible innovation not only requires more or better dissemination of information, or a more elaborate risk assessment, but it requires the acknowledgment of different (moral) viewpoints of stakeholders, which should be taken as a point of departure to identify and to construct shared solutions. A societally responsible

development of energy projects requires the accommodation of the variety of stakeholders’ values. We will first identify and operationalize these public values at stake. The Netherlands will be used as a case study. It is an important European country in natural gas discussions and it is the second largest producer of natural gas in Europe. It is anticipated that there could be substantial amounts of unconventional gas present, while proposals for explorations have been submitted. Since then there has been a fierce public debate between the proponent and opponents of conventional gas, from which we obtain our rich empirical insights.

Method & analysis

The data used for the analysis in this paper are taken from the Dutch public debate on shale gas. Two separate studies have been performed. The first study aims to identify the range of values that are (implicitly and explicitly) present in the Dutch shale gas debate. The second study aims to add a dynamic perspective, by looking into the changes in discourses over time.

(2)

2 The first study consisted of three steps. In the first step, a database of arguments that are used by Dutch stakeholders was created. For the analysis a snowballing strategy was used. Analysis started with key documents from the National Government, NGOs, Industry, and the Dutch Energy Council. References cited in these reports were scrutinized in a next step. This process continued until saturation of arguments was reached. In addition, the aim was to ensure that all actor perspectives were covered in the arguments. In the second step, values were allocated to each of the arguments that were put forward in the debate. Values were identified in an iterative process, going back and forth from empirics to ethical theory. Sometimes multiple values were allocated to a single

argument. For example, the argument The fracking fluid of shale gas exploration can bring

radioactivity from the subsurface above ground, refers to both the value ‘health & safety’ as well as

‘environmental friendliness’. The third step entailed an analysis of the value structure in the Dutch shale gas debate. We distinguish two types of values: substantive and procedural values. Both types of values can be subdivided in a number of more specific values (see Figure 1). Building on Van de Poel (forthcoming), a value hierarchy is constructed (consisting of public values on the highest level, norms derived from these values at the intermediate level and the very specific design requirements at the lowest level of this pyramid). This is done to see on what level controversies are constituted.

Figure 1 Substantive and procedural values in the Dutch shale gas debate

The second study entailed an analysis of discourses over the course of the debate. A media analysis was performed based on 497 newspaper articles from the LexisNexis database using the search word ‘schaliegas’ (Dutch for shale gas). The search was limited to a period of 30 months: November 2010 to April 2013. An event history analysis was performed to identify events (physical events such as earthquakes due to natural gas drilling, as well as actions by particular stakeholders, such as sending out a petition) that may have influenced discourse changes. The software package T-lab was used to identify discourses and discourse developments. T-lab uses linguistic and statistical tools to analyse texts, such as newspaper articles. In order to identify the different discourses a thematic cluster analysis was run. The cluster analysis reveals the most important themes of the arguments used over a period of time. The software provides a list of elementary contexts which are typical to a cluster. These contexts were read to identify the most dominant discourse within the cluster. To reveal more developments the dataset was split up into eight separate episodes in the public debate. For each of the eight episodes a thematic cluster analysis was performed. Ten semi-structured interviews with experts on the shale gas debate were conducted to validate and supplement the results.

(3)

3

Preliminary findings

Our analysis so far points to at least three findings. First, the controversy on shale gas is not so much a value conflict, but rather a ‘value-translation’ conflict. That is, proponents and opponents adhere to the same values, yet the way they translate and conceptualize these values differs. Conflict

furthermore arises due to different trade-offs between values. Second, the debate on shale gas revolves around a broad range of values, that include not only values with regard to the technology itself, but also with regard to the decision making procedure and the institutions relevant to shale gas development. A range of arguments points for example to the limitations of current deliberative and legislative frameworks. This finding is especially relevant, given that the Dutch government as well as the European Commission positions ‘decarbonisation’, security of supply, and

competitiveness as its pillars for energy policy. These pillars relate to the substantive values

‘sustainability’, ‘security of supply’ and ‘welfare’. Our findings suggest that these substantive values do not cover all values that are relevant for energy policy. A policy based on these pillars neglects the importance of procedural values, such as fairness and justice, for responsible innovation.

Interestingly, these procedural values are present in arguments from both opponents and proponents. Third, the way arguments, and thus values, are articulated in a public debate is a dynamic and emergent process. That means that it is not possible to identify ex ante all values that are at stake for the stakeholders involved, as particular values become salient in response to particular events or developments. For example, the analysis shows that the ‘Safety and

Environment’ discourse, which was the basis for the governmental initiated research, impeded actors to learn about the diversity of perspectives and discourses of various actors. As a result, it triggered actors to use a ‘Procedural Justice’ discourse to get through to policy makers.

Implications for responsible innovation

Based on our findings we will be able to derive the requirements of an approach for responsible innovation that allows for 1) making explicit the translation of values into norms and design

requirements and the conflicts that may occur as a result of this, 2) the inclusion and articulation of procedural values in an early stage, 3) dynamic articulation and translation of values.

We build on the Value Sensitive Design (VSD) approach that has primarily been introduced to incorporate public values into human computer interaction (Friedman and Kahn Jr 2000, 2002; Van den Hoven 2007). Later, VSD was elaborated to address the inclusion of values in other domains of technological design (Nissenbaum 2005; Van de Poel 2009b; Van den Hoven et al. Forthcoming; Taebi and Kloosterman Forthcoming). VSD aims to create a technological design that adequately

incorporates the relevant public values. The solutions are sought in the realm of technological adjustment (i.e. through design changes). Yet, our analysis suggests that VSD needs to be expanded to include not only the design of technology, but also the design of institutions, and the design of

procedures for stakeholder interaction.

In the case of shale gas, we can investigate whether seemingly conflicting values can be reconciled through technological modification. For example, since water is scarce in many places, using it in large quantities may raise concern. The chemicals in fracking fluids may also evoke concern, since their seepage into drinking water may constitute a health and safety risk. Inquiry into technological modification therefore needs to focus on finding ways to accommodate health and safety values as

(4)

4 well as resource durability of both energy and water (Taebi, Correljé, Cuppen, Dignum, & Pesch, forthcoming).

Technological development takes place in specific institutional contexts, involving particular stakeholder dynamics. The institutional context incorporates two main categories: i) formal institutions such as laws, standards, regulations and contracts, and ii) informal institutions such as customs, traditions and routines. These institutions embody values that have important ramifications for the distribution of the real or perceived burdens and gains of a specific project. Many of these institutions, especially the formal ones, may be subjected to redesign to accommodate divergent values (Correljé and Groenewegen 2009; Taebi, Correljé, Cuppen, Dignum, & Pesch, forthcoming). Indeed, public values are not static entities frozen by technologies and institutions. They emerge or may turn fluid under the pressure of dynamic social processes. Their fluidity suggests that if we are to incorporate public values into VSD, we need to carefully design decision-making procedures that facilitate constructive forms of stakeholder interaction (Taebi, Correljé, Cuppen, Dignum, & Pesch, forthcoming). Hence, an ideal approach of responsible innovation should build upon extensive research and experience with participatory procedures in policy and planning (Hisschemöller and Cuppen Forthcoming; Rowe and Frewer 2005), as well as the literature on participatory and constructive assessment (e.g., Schot 1992; Joss and Bellucci 2002).

In short, responsible innovation requires interdisciplinary research (Taebi, Correljé, Cuppen, Dignum, & Pesch, forthcoming). We suggest that responsible innovation can be realized by involving,

alongside science and engineering: i) the ethics of technology, to investigate the role of values in technological design; ii) institutional theory, to understand the role of institutions in the realization of values; and iii) the policy, planning and STS literature, to focus on stakeholder engagement.

References

Bell, D., Gray, T., & Haggett, C. (2005). The 'social gap' in wind farm siting decisions: explanations and wind farm responses. Environmental Politics, 14, 460-477.

Correljé, A., Cuppen, E., Dignum, M., Pesch, U., & Taebi, B. (2014). Responsible Innovation in Energy Projects: Values in the Design of Technologies, Institutions and Stakeholder Interactions. In J.Van den Hoven, E. J. Koops, T. Swierstra, H. Romijn, & I. Oosterlaken (Eds.), Responsible Innovation, Volume 2: Concepts,

Approaches, and Applications. Springer.

Friedman, B. and P. H. Kahn Jr. 2000. New directions: A Value-Sensitive Design approach to augmented reality, Proceedings of the conference Proceedings of DARE 2000 on Designing augmented reality environments: 163-164.

Friedman, B. and P. H. Kahn Jr. 2002. Human values, ethics, and design, Proceedings of the conference The human-computer interaction handbook: 1177-1201.

Nissenbaum, H. 2005. Values in technical design. Encyclopedia of Science, Technology and Society, ed. by C.

Mitcham, MacMillan, New York.

Roeser, S. (2011). Nuclear energy, risk, and emotions. Philosophy & Technology, 24, 197-201.

Taebi, B., Correljé, A., Cuppen, E., Dignum, M., & Pesch, U. (forthcoming). Responsible innovation as an endorsement of public values: the need for interdisciplinary research. Journal of Responsible Innovation.

(5)

5 Taebi, B. and J. L. Kloosterman. Forthcoming. Design for Values in Nuclear Technology. In Handbook of Ethics,

Values, and Technological Design, edited by J. Van den Hoven, P. Vermaas and I. Van de Poel. Dordrecht:

Springer:

Van de Poel, I. forthcoming. Translating values into design requirements. In Philosophy and Engineering:

Reflections on Practice, Principles and Process, edited by D. Mitchfelder, N. McCarty and D. E. Goldberg.

Dordrecht Springer:

Van de Poel, I. R. 2009b. Values in Engineering Design. In Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences, edited by A. Meijer. Amsterdam: Elsevier: 973-1006.

Van den Hoven, J. 2007. ICT and value sensitive design. The Information Society: Innovation, Legitimacy, Ethics

and Democracy In honor of Professor Jacques Berleur sj: 67-72.

Van den Hoven, J., I. R. Van den Poel and P. Vermaas. Forthcoming. Handbook of ethics and values in

technological design. Dordrecht: Springer.

Wolsink, M. (2006). Invalid theory impedes our understanding: A critique on the persistence of the language of NIMBY. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, 31, 85-91.

Wynne, B. (2001). Creating public alienation: Expert cultures of risk and ethics on GMOs. Science as Culture, 10, 445-481.

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

We note that the work in this section allows us also to handle the case b = 3 here, but we have chosen to indicate the proof of the case b = 3 separately in the previous

The Energiewende policy is, at the same time, an effective tool for pursuing Germany’s 

ludzi należy brać pod uwagę przede wszystkim interesy innych ludzi, 14,5% - że są ważniejsze interesy innych ludzi, ale mimo to własnych interesów nie na­ leży

opis tutaj jest, można powiedzieć inwentaryzatorski, staszic rzeczywiście kaplica po kaplicy – ko- lejno notuje co się w nich znajduje bez specjalnych odniesień do odczuć ja-

1980.. Вот характерная точка зрения: „Лермонтов, как известно, одну из своих ранних драм назвал Странный человек. Разные бывают странные люди. В

19 In this method, a real-time feedback-controlled current of elec- trons is passed through the nanowire and used to displace the gold atoms (for the electromigration curve of

jednometrowych eksploracja odbywa się przez odkrawywanie terenu za pomocą gęstych przekrojów. Jest to postępowanie o wiele dokład- niejsze, aniżeli na wykopaliskach w Wilnie.

“connected”, so that for instance A s is the collection of all solid sets that.. are either open or closed and C c is the family of closed connected sets. In this section we