• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

Is Linguistics a prerequisite to philosophizing?

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Is Linguistics a prerequisite to philosophizing?"

Copied!
18
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing?

There are three different provinces of philosophical in te re st:

reality, thought, and language. Classical philosophy has always been interested in arriving at an ultim ate understanding of the real world, but the effort to understand the world in ultim ate term s has not always been correctly carried out and free of error.

Here erro r and discussion rather than agreement in interpreta­

tion are the norm. Descartes and the thinkers who appeared after him were of the opinion th at the object to be explained in philosophy is « ideas ». Now ideas can be conceived of in various ways, inasmuch as the content of knowledge is given to m an precisely in « ideas ». However, from the beginning of the tw entieth century the object of philosophical interest shifted, especially in the English-speaking world, to language, since lan­

guage articulates all thought and there is no way to escape from language Q.

0 Linguists who follow F. de Sausure in distinguishing between

« language — le langage » and « speech — la parole », and thus between language as a semiotic system and concrete language or speech, think that it is impossible to extricate oneself from language, but such a stand is surely a « dogm a», since « le langage» is a system of signs which have been produced by man as he knows reality and establishes signs by virtue of an operation of human nature.

We do this consciously, in the function of the primordial sign cons­

truction which is the production of senses or meanings in knowledge.

Furthermore, this is immensely important, we posses signless cognitive contact when we affirm the existence of a concrete being given to us in the empiria or experience of every day and also in our experience of our own (respective) self, since I ceaselessly register the fact that it is

« I » who know, feel, breathe. I affirm the existence of my « I » as a subject in the « act of subjectivizing » human activities.

(2)

186 M. A. Krapiec, O.P

To backtrack a little, after Condillac, it had also seemed to Destutt de Tracy and his confreres, th at ideology — « sciences des idees » — is the general science, and that it constitutes the starting point for all the other sciences, and that it is the basis especially for psychology and morality. Ideology was intended to replace metaphysics. However, Napoleon Bonaparte, who had been a supporter of the school of the ideologues », upon attaining power, dissolved this school as being atheistic, as a

« tenebreuse metaphysique » which was at odds w ith the law and spirit of the nation. « Ideology » in a different form lingered on in other places... (2).

Thus when in recent decades linguistics underwent such an explosive development, some linguists, even such outstanding ones as. E. Benveniste, thought that they could dispense with certain metaphysical questions, even such questions as the « con­

cept » of the self, since the pronoun « I » does not present any content (as David Hume had already brought to attention), that

thus the « I » is only an interiorization of the structure of the gram m ar of a language (3). Even before Benveniste, it had been noted th at the sentential conjunction « is » in principle appears

((only)) (*) in Indoeuropean languages and that it is unknown in other language groups. Thus all metaphysics is a m isunder­

standing constructed around « is ». Linguists have been making

(2) Cf. R. R omberg, Ideologie, in « Historisches Worterbuch der Phi­

losophic », Bd. IV, p. 174 ss. iSchwabe Verlag, Basel.

(3) By « natural language» I basically understand the language of every day life, common sense language, which is the base and point de depart in the formation of the various sciences and which constitutes the basic tool used in philosophical interpretations, of course after philo­

sophical terms have been more closely defined. This is subj ect-predicate language, 'linked with our spontaneous understanding of the reality of

the real world, that is of being as an existing subject composed in itself.

We know this being « responsibly », that is truly, by way of judgements, the most perfect human act of cognition which may be rendered in sentences. In sentences we pronounce about a « subject» various « pre­

dicates », « real features » known in the subject, and we join them in a judgemental predication with the subject by the sentential conjunction

« is » or equivalent grammatical categories.

(*) Double parentheses indicate expressions inserted by the trans­

lator for the sake of clarity.

(3)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 187

forays into the area of philosophy and will continue to do so, all the more as classical philosophy makes use of so called

« natural language » (4) as a tool in its analyses concerning being, which analyses are philosophical in character, not linguistic- How then is language related to philosophy? For isn't this the entire problem in how linguists are related to philosophy? If linguists want to « be related to philosophy » then they have to be philosophers.

Before we undertake to « establish » the borders between linguistics and philosophy we should first consider the ontic character of language, since this is the deciding factor in any effort to penetrate philosophical and linguistic problems.

Now language is without doubt a system of signs, and these signs are heterogenous. Most clearly there appear here also the {(various systems of)) conventional and instrum ental signs, such as various languages, national speech, or language groups, for example, Indoeuropean, Turanian, Vietnamese et cetera. Lan­

guage, as a system of conventional signs involves three inter­

dependent relations, syntactic, semantic and pragmatic. Linguists are interested above all in the syntactic relations of language and sometimes are prone to undervalue language's most essential aspect, the fact that language is a ((system of)) signs; they are sometimes prone also to undervalue or even to deliberately pass over semantic and pragmatic relations (5). Meanwhile, if language is separated from its most primitive and basic relation which is the semantic relation, it will no longer even be recognizable

as language.

The semantic aspect of languages involves another system of linguistic signs, a system very im portant for cognition, namely

(4) I noted this topic in « Language and the Real W orld» (J?zyk i swiat realny). Lublin, 1985.

(5) Perhaps it is easiest to analyze the syntactic aspect of language, as a homogeneous object characterized by its own peculiar structure, the rules of which can be more and more precisely formulated, but this same syntactic aspect would not function at all as a language unless essentially joined with the semantic and pragmatic aspect, because lan­

guage is by its essence a SIGN, from whose nature we cannot abstract without running the risk of losing the object itself.

(4)

188 M. A. Krapiec, O.P.

the system of transparent signs, of the meanings or senses, the concepts and the judgements which create the very content of knowledge. The senses of our spoken and w ritten language are natural transparent signs which, as a system, reveal the essential mode of our knowledge. At the same time thei point to various

cognitive aspects, namely w hat we grasp — from the thing itself and in what m anner we grasp it. Nonetheless, in our spontaneous knowledge it is not the senses of our linguistic expressions which are the object of knowledge, but rather these expressions indi­

cate the manner in which we selectively make our way to the thing itself which is being cognized. The history of philosophical thought is full of instances where thought slipped into an out-of­

control skid, where this system of transparent signs, the system of our concepts, judgements and reasonings itself was taken for the proper object of our (spontaneous) hum an cognition. This was the case w ith Plato, and later with Descartes and the whole philosophy of the subject, particularly in phenomenology. None­

theless we are aware that the senses of our spontaneous know­

ledge, i.e. of our concepts, judgements and reasonings become known only in the act of reflection upon our spontaneous cog­

nition.

Finally the third system of « linguistic signs » is the thing itself as the object of our knowledge, the thing which is signi­

fied » or m arked out by our meanings (natural signs) and this accessible to our intellect. The concrete thing in being known has « meaning » in our knowledge when it is accessible in the light of our natural signs, in the light of concepts and judgments.

What indeed do I understand from a concrete dog as it stands before me? Not very much in proportion to w hat I don't know

in the case of the dog- Indeed I know th at he is a certain kind

of mammal, a quadruped, that he barks, that he is a German

Shepherd. The entire « rem ainder » of the canine organism, of

the canine psyche is inaccessible to me. It becomes accessible

only in the measure in which it has been m arked out, «signified®,

by my acts of cognition and only in the measure in which it

posses cognitive « meaning » for me. Be that as it may, I know

the dog itself and not my concepts and my judgements about

(5)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 189

the dog. Now when I cry out « dog! » everybody looks around for this object, and if they do not see him, they ask « where? ».

In such a case no one asks me about my understanding of « dog ».

It is in this sense that I can speak of the system of linguistic signs in the third case, in the case of the real object of my know­

ledge. Indeed, if reality is not « signed » by some system of cognitive signs, it does not have any cognitive values. From the point ((of view of)) cognition such a reality is « meaningless », for it has not been marked out or « signed - a t » and thus is not accessible in knowledge and in linguistic - cognitive communi­

cation.

As we consider the above distinctions made w ith regard to the system of those signs which are linked w ith our knowledge, we see that language itself oannot be abstracted from the three­

fold system of signs, namely, 1) of conventional signs which are the instrum ents of our speech, 2) of natural signs or the senses of spoken language and 3) of the thing which is signed as the subject of knowledge and the object of language itself. If the bond between these three systems of signs is dissolved, the lan­

guage itself and its essential functions in hum an life are de­

stroyed. Of course this does not prevent linguists from taking some l« isolated » or « far-flung » region of language, for example, its syntactical aspect, for the particular object of their investiga­

tions. This is even necessary if precise analyses are to be carried out. But it m ust at the same time be kept in mind that this is an artificial operation, as it were a « dissection ». It is not poss­

ible for language aver to function in the artificial, laboratory conditions of analysis, ju st as it is impossible for a hand to work when we are breaking it down in the dissecting room into its elementary parts.

When analyzing language as a sign we m ust pay particular attention to the situation in which signs first arise. This situ­

ation is fundam ental if we are to understand a sign, and conse­

quently if we are to understand language itself as a system of signs. The first and principal sign for us is our « co n cep t»

which we form as we come to know the thing. A concept is of

its very nature a sign as a sign; one cannot understand other

(6)

190 M. A. Krapiec, O.P

signs without referring to the understanding of th t sign which is our concept- Our concept is a transparent sign of the thing known. The concept does not hold ((our)) cognitive attention, but guides our spontaneous cognition to the object. The con­

cept fulfills, as it were, the function of special glasses which help the eyes to see the thing itself. As a sign the concept is

« transparent », in principle it directs the act of cognition to the thing signified; nonetheless the act of knowledge, as a spiri­

tual act is « diffracted » and, as it were, forms a « cognitive after­

glow » whenever spontaneous cognition occurs. Indeed, when I know a thing in an act of spontaneous cognition, at the same time i« I know that I am cognizing ». Concomitant reflection does not possess the object, since this reflection registers the very course which cognition takes. Now concomitant reflection, which is intensified in the measure in which the acts of spon­

taneous cognition are repeated, is the basis for actual reflection, that is, for the act of reflection as a special act of cognition, when I take my acts of cognition themselves as the object of my cognition. To be sure, my being able to objectivize my mode of spontaneous cognition witnesses to the fact that in acts of spontaneous, objectivized cognition, the mode of cognition is registered in concomitant reflection. As a result I can take as the object of my cognition my concepts ((themselves)) which have been registered somehow in spontaneous cognition thanks to concomitant reflection. As has been already mentioned, con­

comitant reflection is not something given to us embryonically.

It grows together with acts of cognition. And during reflective life, this reflection grows so excessively, that sometimes it blocks the very activity of man. Perhaps this is the reason why those thinkers who analyze hum an cognition ultimately failed to notice the « slip » and, as it were, « displacement » from the position of concomitant reflection to actual reflection, and they suppose that the object of hum an cognition is precisely the « world of ideas » « the world of things as it is given to us in concepts ».

As a result, the hum an intellect is locked within a world of symbols as Cassirer consistently thought.

It is very im portant in our analysis of hum an language, for

(7)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 191

us to keep in mind, that the world of things which are designated by signs, and not significative transparent signs, constitute the object of m an’s spontaneous cognition. Signs, which come forth in the form of « concepts », best show the nature of the sign itself as a « relational agglomeration ». For, in fact, there can be observed in the concept, which is « the first sign », relations to things, to the subject i.e. the man who possesses the concept, to the one adressed in speech, to the system of other transparent signs and conventional signs. Indeed from a cognized thing only certain features are grasped- Either ((these are grasped simply because)) I am able to grasp them, or ((because)) they are necessary to me for something. From the features which I grasp I construct for myself a « concept »; I myself construct the concept, and thereby, as it were, I « embody » my cognitive act in a constructed sign-concept; this sign is ordered to another person (or to myself as « another »), to whom I « communicate » my cognitive result. This result, the sign-concept, is not isolated from other sign-concepts; rather, it is genetically connected with them in the process of cognition and sign construction. Last of all, this sign is connected with spoken language, and thus w ith a system of conventional, purely linguistic signs. Thus the ag­

glomeration of relations which comes forth in the form ation of a basic transparent sign is obvious. This agglomeration which makes its appearance in the form of a concept, which concept is the sense of linguistic expressions, is the very « s o u l»

of language; it is language's raison d ’etre. Thus the Polish poet Stowacki was on the right track when he wrote: « W hat I w ant is for my nimble tongue ((or language)) to say all th at the head thinks... ». Language is to be fitted to thought and is at the service of thought. The Polish poet Mickiewicz also knew this problem, when he observed in « The Great Improvization » that

« Language lies to the voice, and the voice lies to thought;

Thought flies quickly in the soul, but is shattered in words.

Words engulf thought and totter and quake upon thought just

as the earth over a hidden river which it has swallowed. Do

not people search the depths of their thought after a trem or of

the earth: where is it hurrvins off to. Do thev guess? ».

(8)

192 M. A. Krapiec, O.P

There is still another im portant m atter w ith regard to know­

ledge, signs and language. Namely, there are two situations, in which, as we cognize, we do not create any signs, even transpa­

rent ones; we are not able to create them for we do not come into contact here with any content, inasmuch as content is the arrangement of a thing's features. These are acts of intellectual affirmation, that something exists, that we are dealing with something real and not illusory. Reality « attacks » me with its entire endowment of content, but we know th at existence is neither a feature nor a sum of features- Existence cannot be affirmed by way of sensile « ennumerations » of features, nor by way of any « protocol sentences ». The fact of existence is pri­

mordial and it is not until something exists that it is a real

« thing »; contents come into being and go out of being under actual existence, and not vice versa (with the exception of works of art, but in such a case there is no subjective, substantial ex­

istence). The second situation where it is not possible to con­

struct any sign, even a transparent one, is the existence of the self, the « I », which when symbolized by a personal pronoun is destitute of any content. With regard to our cognition and our language (the use of language) it is of great moment that we possess « immediate and signless » cognitive contact w ith existence as it is given to us, on the one hand, in the world of sense experience and on the other hand, in the very cognizing subject, where my own « I » is present existentially in every act which I register as being subj ectivized (in the act of subjectivi- zation) in the « I ». (By the existential presence of the « I » I mean th a t I immediately experience that I exist but do not know who I am in my nature.) The fact that the existence of a thing and of one's own « I » is affirmed w ithout the mediation of any sign serves as a guarantee for the cognitive realism of those contents which are grasped o r prehended in all other acts of cognition. Indeed I possess a constantly real power for chec­

king w hether the contents which I cognize are « real » and I

do not stand in need of any « Cartesian proof » as to the value

of my knowledge, for I never cease from distinguishing those

contents which can be said to exist only abstractly from really

(9)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 193

existing contents (6). This is also the reason for the « pseudo­

problems » proper to scepticism of various provenances.

While keeping in mind natural language as a system of signs, which signs have a mediatory role in our knowledge of reality and in the communication of cognitive results, we should still call to mind some traditional doctrines of the topic of the media'

tion of language, as a sign system in hum an knowledge. These doctrines go back to the middle ages. Various types of linguistic- cognitive mediation were differentiated:

1) The « Medium per quod » and « medium ex quo » refer to language as the vehicle of a philosophical or scientific theory

and to language as it is organized into a system of reasoning, whose symbol is the syllogism. Thus the « medium through which » events o r the structure of things are known is a phil­

osophical or scientific theory; in order to acquire a knowledge of certain facts, for example, vestigial organs in living organisms, one m ust first take into consideration the theory of biological evolution, which in an appropriate way explains the facts ob­

served; it perm its us to understand them. Likewise the « me­

dium ex quo », reasoning, which is symbolized by the syllogism, m ust be known beforehand, just as the premises m ust be known prior to the conclusion.

2) The « medium quod » as an interm ediary is an express­

ion, whether belonging to a natural or to an artificial language, which also draws to itself cognitive attention, for the under­

standing of the sense of this term makes possible to understand­

ing of the thing itself. One m ust « learn » the expressions of a given language in order to understand the object designated. It was said of this intermediary « quod cognitum, in cognitionem alterius d u c it» — « when it is known, it leads to the knowledge of another ».

(6) The problematic of being's existence made its appearance for good, after Avicenna, in Saint Thomas Aquinas, but has been developed and

has shown its consequences in metaphysics and epistemology in recent decades.

(10)

194 M. A. Krapiec, O.P.

3) « Medium in quo », namely an intermediary « in which » we see the thing itself. This is a concept, th at is, a transparent

sign, which in spontaneous cognition does not hold our atten­

tion directly, but which is an essential component of our cogni­

tion. As was mentioned above, this sign is noticed only « in­

cidentally », since I can objectivize it in an act of reflection and I can find out exactly what this concept means as a transparent sign, as a m anner of our intellectual cognition of the thing itself*

The « medium in quo » as the meaning of linguistic expressions always makes its appearance in natural language, since w ithout it hum an speech would not be hum an speech at all.

4) The « medium quo » — an intermediary, in whose light the content of a thing is known. One m ust determine a cogni­

tive aspect and so select acts of cognition, so as to determine for oneself through their harmony a clear « angle of vision » with regard to the object Just as light is necessary if the vision is to be able to see colour, so also an appropriate harmony of acts is necessary in cognizing in a determinate way some object.

In the tradition of scholastic philosophy this natural « medium quo » was the « species im p ressa», the « impressed im ag e»

which determines cognition and is expressed in the « species ex- pressa », namely, the concept. This « expressed image » is never noticeable, not even in reflective cognition. Nonetheless its ex­

istence renders the determined cognition of some object free of contradiction.

5) Finally in the act of cognition we possess a sign-less contact w ith the thing's or the « I »’s act of existence, of the

« I » as « a subject in the act of subjectivizing ». This cognitive contact of my existing acts of cognition w ith the act of exist­

ence, which act primordially releases the process of cognition is a « superintelligible » and « superaletheic » situation, for it is the reason for the cognizability of acts of cognition. W ithout such a signless cognitive contact with existence as the act of being, there would be no basis for distinguishing real states

from nonreal states.

The traditional concept of sign mediation presented here

(11)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 195

refers above all to language. Language’s mediation is not uni­

vocal and it possesses its own various modes and degrees. Philo­

sophers have long ago been aware of the facts connected with language's role as a medium. This is born out by Aristotle's treatise « On the sentence »,

P e r i H e r m e n e i a s ,

and numerous commentaries on this work both in the ancient world and in

the middle ages, for example, the commentary of Ammonius, which was translated by William of Moerbeke for Thomas Aqui­

nas, who was probably the first to draw upon this enormous commentary. Precisely in keeping with this tradition, with common sense and the nature of philosophy itself as it ultim a­

tely explains being, we should explain language as a being which is a system of signs. Hence also the understanding of the sign, of its structure and its prim ordial « meaning » is fundamental aven for linguistic science. Thus upon the canvas of the « ontol­

ogy » of knowledge, more strictly speaking, of the metaphysics of knowledge, there appears the essential understanding of the sign system. The sign and its structure depend upon the struc­

ture of the being which is designated and upon the being (man as he cognizes) who « signs » and creates the sign. Generally speaking, it is the structure of being as this structure is known which m ust be expressed in the sign or language, and as a m atter of principle one should not posit anything about reality from the point of view of a sign or language, for then nothing at all will be explained about reality.

Now it is true that the structure of natural language can be of help in understanding reality itself, but it is neither the only, nor the chief route of cognition. It is only auxiliary, for being is not dependent upon any sign, but a sign is dependent upon a being- Aristotle and Porphyrius, Plotinus's secretary, were both aware th at our language in its structure and its cog­

nitive - communicative function « im itates » reality and is a pe­

culiar « reflection » of reality. Porhpyrius in a masterly fashion called this to attention in his « Eisagoge » to Aristotle's Catego­

ries. For, having in mind the structure of composite being, he

observed that the parts which « compose » being are sometimes

constitutive parts, sometimes nonconstitutive, changing, liable

(12)

196 M. A. Krapiec, O.P

to destruction, and thus accidental (although here too we can differentiate those necessary accidents which are linked together by necessity and « intrinsically » with the nature of a thing, or

only « extrinsically » and in a purely changeable way). The struc­

ture of being, when it is known in a hum an way and expressed in an act of perfect cognition, namely a judgement expressed externally in the form of a « sign-proposition » (although not every sentence or proposition is strictly speaking a sign of a judgement as judgement), is, as it were, « m irrored » in the

« m aterial » composition of the judgement out of subject and predicate. The predicate reveals the component parts of the subject (whether it be an individual or an abstract). It is man who, in his act of cognition, is the one who joins the predicate with the subject by means of a sentential copula, and carries out the act of predication.

Predicates can be « joined » with the subject, that is, they can become « predicables » in various ways. One can « read out » those parts of the subject which are called « genus », « species »,

« specific difference », « property » and « accident ». Thus sen­

tential predicates can reveal the structure of being and at the same time reveal the m anner in which the parts of a being are joined into one existing subject. I wrote at greater length about this in my book « J?zyk i swiat realny », Language and the real world®, where I analyzed the objective aspect of language(7).

Long before they developed the skills of reading and writing, people knew the structure of being, since they were able to create tools. Being's act of existence is precisely in the structure of being. Existence cannot be thought of as a « feature » of a thing w ithout falling into absurdity, neither can it be contained in a sign. Yet it is the « reason » for reality itself; w ithout exist­

ence there would be no real being, no nature, essence, nor any of the real component « features » of essence. In our language we m ust advert also to the act of existence. In philosophy we

(7) Especially the first part of my monograph is dedicated to the problematic of language in a philosophical perspective. There also I

discuss and ground in a broader way to the matters raised in this article.

(13)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 197

m ust perceive existence s function of making being real. This m ust be expressed in our language. This is precisely w hat we do in an existential, predicateless judgement, for existence can­

not be conceptualized; it cannot be expressed in the form of a sign; it cannot become the predicate of a sentence, for it does not carry any new inform ational content about the subject. Can we abandon all this in our philosophical explanation of the world

because the linguists who ride a syntactical horse in their treat­

m ent of language are not able to bring this « horse » to a holt by the spring of sign-making and give the horse to drink of the

w ater of meaning?

Language itself — whether it be in the group of Indoeuro- pean languages, or Turanian, or some other, cannot leave off seeing and communicating the existential aspect of language, namely from connotation of the realism of the objects of the real world- Yet, as has been known for a long time,. this is not always done by a sentential « is » (the functions of which are various), b u t ((sometimes)), by way of appropriate language structures, for example, by suffixes and prefixes, or, as in the Russian language, by sentence stru c tu re : for example, « ty vor »

— « you thief » where there isn't any « is », but everyone, espe­

cially the defendant, understands of this sentence well enough.

These m atters are already well-known and in general they do not play a deciding role w ith regard to the structure of reality, nor should they be regarded as decisive in this respect.

It is worse when philosophers of certain philosophical orien­

tation (analytic philosophers) would like to pass judgement on reality on the basis of language’s syntactic function. W hat takes place, and not w ithout the influence of linguistics, is a confusion of reason and consequence in explaining the world. For if lan­

guage is a system of signs, and signs are produced by man to

« designate » (our knowledge of things) in some strictly deter­

mined aspect, then it is first necessary to know things, and ((then)) signs are introduced to designate them. Although trans­

parent signs make it possible to know things, still it is not signs, but the thing which is the object of our first spontaneous know­

ledge; signs and their structure can become legible in reflective

knowledge.

(14)

198 M. A. Krapiec, O.P.

|

From this there follows the general conclusion, that lan­

guage does not decide about the structure of reality, but rather reality is given to us first, since otherwise it would be imposs­

ible to make anly sign for it and consequently it would be im­

possible to create any language as a system of signs. I t is well and true that analyses of languages can help us sometimes to avoid posing pseudo-problems, that such analyses may help us to show more precisely the very structure of reality, but the analysis of language and of our knowledge of the rules of the syntactic meaningfulness of language still does not make it poss­

ible to resolve philosophical problems nor does it show us the

w

very structure of being. One m ust have a view of being, and not merely a view of the sign, in order to make a judgement on being.

As we move on to the polemical section of our considera­

tions on linguistics and philosophizing, we cannot, in the light of the above analyses, agree w ith the position that linguistics is a prerequisite for philosophizing. Philosophy and its pro­

blems constitute the most ancient stratum of organized human knowledge and the possess their own value independent of lin­

guistics. Furtherm ore, by virtue of its method of knowledge acquisition (searching for a unique necessary reason which vould render the facts free of contradiction), philosophy can take lan­

guage as an object; indeed philosophy has done ju st this from the beginning. Linguistics as a rigorous science does a good job of elaborating the syntactic aspect of language, but when it turns to consider the semantic and pragmatic aspect of language not only do its analyses lose in precision, but it also rushes (where angels fear to tread) into the field of philosophy and pronounces common « non-sense » (for example, the negation of the ontic subjectivity of the self on the grounds th at the perso­

nal pronoun « I » is a « contentual vacuum »). Now if linguis­

tics were to stop considering the semantic aspect of language, it would generally cease to be a science about language, which is a system of signs signifying meanings and designating things.

Hence it follows that philosophical analyses of language possess

their own value independently of linguistics and can contribute

(15)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 199

to better determ ination of the object of the science of linguis­

tics, namely, a system of signs. However it cannot be said that analyses carried out on the ground of linguistics are necessary preconditions for the cultivation of philosophy, for this is both historically and methodologically untrue.

Now we shall move on to a selective discussion of certain statem ents made by Alfred Gawronski in his article « When does

‘to be’ mean ‘to exist' »? (Kiedy ‘bye’ znaczy ‘istniec’? ») (8). It should be rem arked that, generally speaking, the author seems

to regard linguistics as a peculiar « a priori » for the meaning­

ful cultivation of philosophy, w ith which we of course cannot agree. Mister Gawronski writes: >« For the many philosophical schools which are concerned with the problem atic of the various functions fulfilled by the verb “to be” in Indoeuropean lan­

guages, how very im portant is the broad and methodologically precise presentation of this problem atic undertaken by the aut­

hors of the monograph “The Foundation of Language”- This pre­

sentation puts an end to the many intuitional and am ateur inter­

pretations of the multifunctional character of this verb such as have appeared until recently in the philosophical works of the

most serious authors ». Does the author indeed think that me­

thodologically precise and wide analyses in the area of linguistics can replace philosophical analyses? Or perhaps that linguistics is an « a priori » for philosophy? Yet in each discipline there are different issues. Are philosophical analyses of the verb « is » am ateur because thev do not consider linguistics? Sometimes

linguistics may problems but « for the

love of God » there is one subject m atter in linguistics and ano­

ther in philosophy. Shortly thereafter the author w rite s: « the analysis of the world as something which can be grasped in the categories of our thought and speech, must begin (the underlin­

ing is mine) by elucidating the various semantic functions played by this verb... ». A hundred times no! Linguistics became an aut­

onomous science only in the tw entieth century and the most distinguished linguists sometimes commit terrible philosophical

(8) ZNAK, 1989, n. 2, 162-174

(16)

200 M. A. Krapiec, O.P.

mistakes. Our understanding of reality, although it be articulated in language, nevertheless is not dependent upon an understanding of syntactics and semantics. This is not any « great philosophical licence of interpretation » (page three), for philosophical inter­

pretation concerns being and language inasmuch as it as a being whose character is that of a sign, which in no way violates the autonomy of linguistics, whose task it is to set forth its own linguistic, but not philosophical, interpretations. These are the specific features of these sciences and linguistics cannot replace philosophy. Whenever it tried to do this it did it badly and not at all with precision but, to be sure, w ith a certain « confusio linguarum ».

The problematic of « generation and transform ation » is an interesting linguistic discovery, but it is in the area of linguistics and does not bear upon the structure of reality, which structure philosophy endeavours to explain. It is reality and its struc­

ture which imposes certain functions onto the verb « is », which, independently of the analyses of linguists, can be reduced to three: cohesion, assertion and affirmation. The division is carried out with respect to the composition of real being, and our cogni­

tive relation to any one being, a being which I know, which is composed of non-identical parts. The fact that the sentential conjunction « is » can take on different forms from the linguistic point of view does not bear upon the structure of reality or our knowledge of this reality. For no m atter how we may call the link between subject and predicate (which is conditioned by, among other things, the history and psychology of language), we are always dealing w ith predicative and nonpredicative sent­

ences, by which we express our knowledge of reality. It is not the case that we w ait for grammarians and linguists; that we wait with anticipation for their form ulations so th at by them we can then « reach » things. Language is not an « a p r io r i»

for knowledge, but only a semiotic system. We m ust never lose sight of the « bilateral » ontic structure of the sign, so th at we may see w hat language’s role is in knowing in general, and in

the philisophical ultim ate kind of knowledge in particular- For

this reason illustration by means of various sentential structures

(17)

Is Linguistics a Prerequisite to Philosophizing? 201

(verbal, nominal, locutional and still others) concerns linguistic m atters but not the structure of being. But we can note in pass­

ing that here we are constantly dealing w ith predicative or pre- dicational sentences. For it is not im portant for the known re­

ality which is in itself composed in a manifold way, whether sentential predicates will be in the gramm atic category of noun, adjective, pronoun etc., for they designate, each in its own way, states of affairs which in judgem ental cognition can be « pre­

dicates » providing inform ation about the structure of being.

This is an embarassing rem inder (as if it were an attain­

m ent of linguistics) of the predicative and referential functions which for centuries have been known as predication and lin­

guistic communication.

The problem of whether or not the division of « is » into

« copulative » and « existential » is correct, and how this division should be philosophically understood is not dependent upon linguistics, but upon the structure of reality as it is known:

only reality and its structure carries any weight here. If some­

one would like to invalidate philosophical analyses concerning being itself and its structure, he should first dem onstrate that the structure of reality is not composite, that the existence of a thing is only one of its features. Thus linguistic and phil­

osophical investigations belong in different levels of analysis, and these m atters cannot be mixed or confused w ithout incurr­

ing grave consequences, unless of course one thinks that lan­

guage is an « a priori » for cognition. The « truth-claim » and the « affirmatio existentiae » are on different levels; the « various existential meanings » on page 197 are a common « ignorantia

elenchi »; this is simply would be

hard to conduct lectures here once again; these m atters m ust known before they can be criticized. Finally, if it is

the tru th function of « is », Aristotle long ago raised tl in the fourth book of his Metaphysics (Met. Gamma) tion w ith how being and the principle of noncontrc to be understood; the tru th function concerns the w;

thought is connected with real, and consequently exis Generally speaking it is difficult for a philosop

m atter of

is

(18)

202 M. A. Krapiec, O.P

analyzing states of reality, and by the same token language in­

asmuch as it is a semiotic system of a specific ontic structure, to carry on a discussion with the field of linguistics, where the syntactic aspect of language is the basis object of research. It is even more difficult to cultivate philisophy on the basis of the findings of linguistics, which for me is absurd for merely me­

thodological reasons. In such a case there may be even more linguistic misunderstandings, or a pseudo-discussion, for it is necessary to be aware of the principal cognitive position in re­

lation to reality. Quite simply « principiis obsta! ».

M. A.

K r a p i e c ,

O P

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

This study investigated the effects of rubber content and warm- mix additives on the storage stability of CRMB binders and explored the dynamic asymmetry between the bitumen-rich

Kawabata i Zeki oraz Vartanian i Goel rejestrowali aktywność mózgu badanych przy użyciu fMRI (funkcjonalny rezonans magnetyczny, wykazu- jący zmiany przepływu krwi i utlenowania

We współczesnej gospodarce zasoby niematerialne wpływają na wzrost wartości przedsiębiorstwa. Są one mocno związane z człowiekiem, ponieważ to on je tworzy w danym

„Iinną częścią religii praw d ziw ej jtest nasza pow inność w obec człow ieka.. A ugustyna, zw ykło

Aby kształcenie to było skuteczne, wykładowcy i studenci potrzebuj ˛ a historii Polski 10 , historii literatury polskiej 11 , gramatyki współczesnej polszczyzny 12 i włas´nie

Konsekwencją tego jest to, że nie obejmują one wszystkich osób zbiorowości etnicznej, rzadko stają się strukturami pośrednimi całego społeczeństwa, a

Also, assuming that as a result of neuromarketing research an entrepreneur (e.g. a trading enterprise) will gain information about the most effective stimuli bringing an