• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

On almost rigid mathematical structures

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "On almost rigid mathematical structures"

Copied!
18
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

A С T A U N I V E R S I Т А Т I S L О D Z 1 E N S I S FOLIA MAT II ЕМ АТ IC А 9, 1997 Л Iiksaiulcr Klmrazishvi li O N A L M O S T R I G I D M A T H E M A T I C A L S T R U C T U R E S W e d is c u s s a c o n c e p t o f an a l m o s t rigid m a t h e m a t ic a l s t r u ct u re a nd a c o n c e p t o f au a lm o s t rigid m a t h e m a t ic a l s t ru c t u r e in t he s t r o n g s en s e. W e c o m p a r e t h es e t w o c o n c e p t s w ith t h e usu al n o t io n o f a rigid m a t h e m a t ic a l st r u c t u r e . W e als o c on s id er a n a p p li c a t io n o f t he in t ro d u c e d c o n c e p t s t o t h e t he o r y o f line ar ly ord ered se t s.

Let S be a. ty p e of a mathem atical structure in the visual sense of N.B ourbaki (see [I])- For exam ple, Ï m a y be the ty pe of a topological structure, the ty pe of a structure of a measurable space, the typ e of an order structure and of m any others.

Suppose that our t yp e S satisfies the following two conditions:

1) for the class of all structures of this ty pe, a class o f morphisms (hom om orphism s) is defined in such a way that we have a category in the standard algebraic sense;

2) if E is a basic set, $ is a structure of the ty p e S defined on E , and X is an arbitrary subset of E, then there exists a structure S x of the same t y pe ^ such that S \ is defined on A and is induced by the original structure Ń.

Condition 2) can be called a hereditarility property of the given structure ty pe S . Notice that topologies, measurable spaces and rela-tion structures satisfy condirela-tion 2). There are also m any other struc-tures for which this condition is fulfilled.

(2)

Let E be again a basic set and let S be som e structure of the type S defined on E. Let us recall that the structure S is rigid if the group of all autom orphism s of .S' is a o ne- ele m e nt set. In other words, the structure .S' is rigid if and only if the identity transformation of the basic set E is a unique automorphism of S .

In a more general situât ion, we say that a structure S on E is alm ost rigid if, for every automorphism / : ( E , $ ) —► ( E , $ ) of this structure onto itself, the inequality

c a r d ( { x G E : J ( x ) ф :r}) < c a r d ( E )

holds. Further, we say that a structure S 011 E is almost rigid in the strong sense if. for every m onom orphism g : ( E , S ) —> ( E , S ) of this structure into itself, the inequality

c a r d ( { x G E : y ( x ) ф .r}) < c n r d ( E )

holds. Let us remark that if a basic set E is finite, then the notion of an almost rigid structure (un E ) may rather frequently coincide with the notion of an almost rigid st ructure in the strong sense. For instance, suppose that £ is the t yp e o f an algebraic structure or the ty pe of a structure of a linearly ordered set, and let .S’ be a structure o f the t yp e £ defined on a finite basic set. E. Then it. can easily be checked that .S' is alm ost rigid if and only if .s' is almost rigid in the strong sense.

Of course, any rigid structure is almost rigid, but the converse as-sertion is not true. It. is clear that any almost rigid structure in the strong sense is alm ost rigid, too. T he following sim ple ex am ple shows us that there exists a graph structure which is almost rigid in the strong sense but is not rigid.

E x a m p l e 1. Let ./• and y be any two distinct elem ents which do not belong to the countable set of integers { 1 , 2 ,. . . , » , , . . .} . Let us put

E = { x , y } U { 1 . 2 ... » , . . . }

a n d le t us d efin e th e gr ap h st r u c tu r e ,S' on th e se t E b y th e fo llo w in g ed g es:

(3)

Then it. is not difficult to check that S is not a rigid structure. At the sa m e tim e S is almost rigid in the strong sense. Moreover, here every m ono morphism of the structure S into itself moves at mo st two elem ents of the basic set E.

Let us notice, in connection with Exa mple 1, tha t a structure of an infinite well ordered set without the last elem ent gives us a sim ple exa m ple of a rigid structure which is not alm ost rigid in the strong sense.

Let E lit* an infinite basic set and let .S' be a structure of the ty pe S defined on E . T h e following two questions naturally arise:

Q u e s t i o n 1. Does there exist a subset .V of the set E with

e a r d ( X ) = c n r d ( E ) such that the structure S x induced on X is rigid?

Q u e s t i o n 2. Does there exist a. subset X of the set E with

c a v d ( X ) = ccird(E) such that the structure S x induced on .V is

al-most rigid (or is alal-most, rigid in the strong sense)?

No tice that Question 1 was extensively investigated by several au-thors for a. topological structure and Question 2 was extensively inves-tigated for a. measurable space struct ure (see, e.g., the article of Shortt [9] and references given in this article).

Let us remark also, in connection with the first, question, that in the most of interesting and im portant situations the answer to this quest ion is negative. In particular, one of such situations is described in the next sim ple exam ple.

E x a m p l e 2. Let us consider the t yp e Ü of a structure of a measur-able space with the additional axiom which says tha t all one-element subsets of a. basic set are measurable. This ty pe o f a structure can often be m et in various domains of m a them a tics, especially in modern analysis and probability theory. Now, let E be an infinite basic, set and let S be a structure of the ty pe S on E . Then it is not difficult to see tha t, for the pair ( E . S ), the answer to Question 1 is negative.

Another sim ple ex a m ple o f such a situation can be obtained if we consider the ty pe S of a structure of a. co m plete graph defined on an infinite basic set.

(4)

T im s, we sec that it is more perspective to investigate Question 2

concerning the ex iste nce of almost rigid (respectively, almost rigid in the strong sense) substructures induced by the original structure .S'. We want to notice, in connection with Question 2, that it is possible to establish some general conditions sufficient for the affirmative solution of the a bo ve -m e ntio ned question (see, for instance, Proposition 1 be-low). Notice also that those general conditions are formulated in terms of partial isomorphisms or in terms of partial monomorphism s o f the given structure .S' (let us recall that e.g. a partial monomorphism is any injective hom omorphism of t he form / : ( V' S y ) —* ( E , .S'), where Y is a subset of E and S y is t he st ruct ure on V induced by the original struc-ture' ,S ). Actually, we can say that one' ol t hose sufficient conditions rep-resents an abstract version of t he purely topological Lavrentiev’s the-orem about extensio ns of Immeomorphisms of subsets of Polish spaces to hom eom orphisms ol С/д-subsets of such spaces. This classical the-orem with its various generalizations and applications is thoroughly considered in the well known monograph of Kuratowski [2].

In order to lormulate Proposition 1 we need a sim ple auxiliary no-tion concerning partial hom omorphism s. Namely, let

/ : ( Y , S y ) -> ( E , S ) , <j : ( Z , S 7j) - » ( E , S )

be any two partial homomorphism s. We shall say that the partial hom omorphism j majorâtes the partial homomorphism y if f is an extension of ц.

P r o p o s i t i o n 1. Let .s' be a s t ru ct u re ou an infinite basic set E a nd

su p p o s e t ha t, ior each subset D o f E w i t h c<ird(D) = c n r d ( E ) , th ere e xi st s a s t r u c t u re S p on D i n d u c ed b y S . S u p p o s e hIs o t h a t t here e xi sts

a f a m il y Ф ol parti al i n o n o m o r p h is m s ( a ctin g from s u bse t s o f E in to E ) sa t i sfy i ng t h e following t wo conditions:

1) c a r d ( Ф) < c a r d ( E ) ;

2) for e ve r y p arti al m o n o m o r p h i s m // : ( Z. S%) —* ( E . S ) . t here is a partial m o n o m o r p h i s m /' £ <|> such that f ma j o râ t e s <j.

Th e n t here e xist s a s ubset Л o f E s at isfy i ng t h e n e x t t wo relations: a) c a r d ( X ) = c a r d ( E ) ;

(5)

Л .К 11Л К A Z IS 11VILI

c ard i n al it y o f t h e set.

{ . r e x : h {x ) Ф .!•} is st ri ct l y less th an t h e c ard in al it y o f X .

Co ns eq u en t ly , t h e s tr u c t u r e S \ is al mo st rigid in th e st ron g sense (in parti cular, this st r u c t u r e is almost, rigid).

Proof. Let O' be the least ordinal number of cardinality c n rd ( E ) .

Obviously, we can represent the family Ф in the form Ф = { f t : £ < « } .

Let us remark that the identity transformation of E belongs to the fam-ily Ф and, without loss o f generality, we may assume that Jo coincides with this transformation. Now, let us define, applying the m ethod of translinite recursion, an injective family

{•'•f : £ < ° }

of elem ents of the basic set E. Suppose that fi < or and a partial family : £ < I } of elem ents of E has already been defined. Let us consider two sets

л = Ш * с ) ■ t < & С < ß } ,

ß = U r ' ( * c ) : £ < / i C < ß } -Evidently, we have I he inequalities

c a r d [A U B ) < 2 ( c a r d ( ß) ) 2 < a i r d ( E ) .

(Consequently, the relation

E \ [ A l i В ) ф

is true. Let х ц be an elem ent of the set E \ [ A U B) .

In such a way we are able to construct the required family { ;rt- : £ < o } of elem ents of E. Now, let us put

(6)

Clearly, c a r d ( X ) = c a r d ( E ) . From the assum ptions of the proposition it follows that there exists a structure S . \ on A iminced by the original structure S . Take an arbitrary m onomorphism

h : (Л". ,S'.v ) —> (A", ,S',v ).

This m onomorphism can be considered as a partial m onom o tphism

g : ( X , S x ) ^ ( E , S ) .

According to condition 2). there exists a partial monomorphism f G Ф such that J m ajorâtes g. Obviously, for som e ordinal number £ < cv, we have / = Taking into account the construction of the set X , it is not difficult to check that the inequality

c a r d ( { x G A : /'(.• (x ) ф .r}) < c a r d ( X )

is fulfilled. We also can write

{.r G A" : /(- г) ф •<’} = {;*• G X : Н ( х ) ф , г } . Hence, we obtain the inequality

<<ir<l({.v G A : h ( x ) ф ./ }) < c a n l ( X ) ,

which shows us that, the structure S \ is almost rigid in the strong sense. 1 bus the prool ol Proposition I is com plete.

Let ( E . S ) be again a sei equipped with a structure of the type H. We say that a m apping of the form

/ : ( Y \ $ y ) —> ( Z . $ z )

is a partial isomorphism (acting from ( E . S ) into ( E , . S')) if Y and Z are som e subsets of E . S y and S z are the structures on these subsets induced by .S’, and J is an isomorphism of the structure S y onto the structure S z

-T he next proposition is analogous to Proposition 1.

P r o p o s i t i o n 2. Lr t S be a st r u c t u r e on an infinite basic set E

(7)

Л . К IIARAZISHVILI

t h ere e xi st s a s t r u c t u re S u on D i n d u ce d b y S . S u p p o se also that, t here e xi st s a f a m il y Ф o f p artial i so mo rp h i s ms ( a ct i ng f rom ( E , S ) in to ( E , S ) ) sa t is f yi n g t h e following t wo conditions:

1) c n rd {Ф) < c a r d ( E ) ;

2) for e v e r y p arti al i so mo rp h i sm д a cti n g from ( E , S ) i n to ( E , S ), t he re is a pa rtia l i so m o r p h i sm f G Ф such t h a t / ma j o râ t es д.

Th e n t here exi st s a su b s et X o f E sa t i sfy i ng t h e following relations: a) c u r d ( X ) = c a r d ( E) ;

b) for an a rb itra ry i so mo r p h i sm h : ( X , S x ) (A’, ,S.\') t h e

cardi-n a l i t y o f t h e sei

{,• G A : h(.r) ф .,■}

is st ri ct l y less t ha n th e car dina lit y o f X .

In particular, t h e st r u c tu re S \ is a l mo s t rigid.

No tice that the proof of Proposition 2 is quite similar to the proof of Proposition I.

R e m a r k I. T he result of Proposition I som etim es can be generalized

to the case of partial morphisms which are not necessarily monomor- phism s. For instance, a direct analogue of Proposition 1 can be true for those partial morphism s which have small preimages (in the sense of cardinality) of the one-elem ent subsets of a basic set E. More precisely, if the cardinality of the set E is regular and all partial morphisms J G Ф satisfy the inequality

c a r d ( f ~ ' ( x ) ) < c a r d ( E ),

for each elem ent x G E . then the analogue of Proposition 1 is true for such partial morphisms, too.

R e m a r k 2. T he assum ption that, for each subset D of E with

c a r d ( D ) = c m i l ( E ) . there exists a structure S o on D induced by S is

rather essential in the formulation of Proposition 1. This can be shown by simple exam ples ol algebraic structures. Indeed, let us consider the set E of all integers equipped with a natural group operation - addition of numbers. It is not difficult to check that in such a case there exists a family Ф of partial m onomorphism s satisfying conditions 1) and 2) of Proposition 1. But there does not exist an infinite subgroup A' of

(8)

E satisfying relations a.) and I)) of the sa me proposition. Moreover, in

this rase all infinite subgroups of the group E are isomorphic to E and the group struct ure of E is not an almost rigid structure in our sense.

R e m a r k S. Let S' be a structure on an infinite basic, set E. Suppose

that, for every subset D ol E, there exists a structure S p on D induced by S . Suppose also that there is a family К of subsets of E sat isfying the following conditions:

1 ) card( A ) < car<l( E):

2) for each set Z belonging to I\ , the cardinality of the family of all m ono morphism s from Z into E is less or equal to c a v d ( E ) \

•'5) for any partial monomorphism

!l : V —> E ( Y С E)

there exists a partial m onomorphism

/ : Z - * E ( Z С E )

such that, Z € Л and / majorat.es //.

1 hen il is easy I o sec I hat I hero exists a family Ф ol part ial m onomo r-phisms satisfying the assum ptions of Proposition 1. ( Consequently, we can assert the existence ol a subset A of the basic set E such that

card( A ) = c n r d ( E ) and the structure ,S'y on A induced by S is almost

rigid in the st rong sense.

Let us notice that the family l\ mentioned above is, as usual, an in-ner object for the given structure .S', i.e. an inin-ner term for .S’, according to the terminology ol Bourbaki (see [ 1 ]). We want to notice also that condition ;5) m ay be considered as an abstract version o f Lavrentiev’s theorem on extensions of lmmeomorphisms.

R e m a r k Let E be an infinite bąsic set. let S be a structure on

E and let Ф be a family of partial morphisms from ( E , S ) into ( E , S )

satisfying the subsequent two conditions:

1) c a r d ( Ф) < c a r d ( E ) :

2) for every partial morphism <j from ( E . S ) into ( E . S ), there is a partial morphism / 6 Ф such that f ma.joral.es //.

(9)

h a v in g th e fo llo w in g p ro p e r ty : for e v e r y set, A' Ç E wi t h c a r d ( X ) = c a r d ( E ) , th e r e str ic tio n o l h to A is n o t a m o r p h ism fro m X i n t o E.

1 he prool ol this lac) is analogous to the proof of Proposition 1. Indeed, applying the m ethod ol transfinite recursion we can construct a m apping h : E —> E so that the inequality

c a rd ({.r G E : h ( x ) = /(.;•)}) < c a r d ( E )

will be true lor each partial morphism f G Ф.

Actually, this construction is due to Sierpiński. More precisely, Sierpiński applied t he construction presented above in a particular sit -uation where 1 is the ty pe of a topological structure and the class of morphism s is the class of all continuous mappings. T h e corresponding result (due to Sierpiński and Zygmund) is formulated as follows: there exists a function

h : R -> R

such that its restriction to any subset A' of R with c a r d ( X ) = c a rd ( R ) is not a continuous m apping (here R denotes the set of all real numbers equipped with the standard order topology).

Notice that an analogous result is also true if we take the class of all Borel mappings as a class of morphisms.

R e m a r k -7. Let. E be an infinite basic set, let ./ be an ideal ol subsets of E and let S be a structure on E.

We say t hat the structure .S' is ./-rigid if, for every automorphism / : ( £ , < . ' ) - ♦ ( £ , < ? )

of this structure o nto itself, we have {.v G E : f ( x ) ф :r} G J .

We say that the structure .s' is ./-rigid in the strong sense if, for every m onomorphism

g : ( E , S ) - * ( E , S )

of this structure into itself, we have {;/■ G E : g ( x ) ф x } G J .

Obviously, the concept of a ./-rigid structure and the co ncept of a J - rigid structure in the strong sense are generalizations of the concepts of a rigid structure, an almost rigid structure and an almost rigid structure

(10)

in the strong sense. Also, it is easy to see that som e generalizations of Propositions 1 and 2 ran be formulated and proved for ./-rigid (./-rigid in the strong sense) m athem atica l structures. Moreover, i f ./ satisfies so m e natural conditions, then a set X can he taken so tha t X ./.

Let us return to alm ost rigid structures and to Question 2 posed at the beginning of the paper. Namely, we wish to discuss here a natural application ol Propositions 1 and 2 to the situation where the ty pe S coincides with the t yp e ol a structure of a Dedekind com plete linearly ordered set, with som e addit ional properties. In t his situation we take the class ol all increasing mappings as a class ol morph isms for our ty pe L. Hence, in this case the class ol all monom orphism s is the class ol all strictly increasing mappings.

A detailed information on linearly ordered sets (and, in particular, on Dedekind co m plete linearly ordered sets) can be found in the well known monograph o f Sierpiński [7].

First let us consider a sit uation where we do not have infinite sub-structures alm ost rigid in the strong sense. Indeed, let, E be the ty pe of a structure ol an infinite well ordered set. Obviously, ^ is sim ul-taneously the ty pe of a structure of an infinite, Dedekind co m plete, linearly ordered set. Let ( E . S ) he an arbitrary infinite set equipped with a structure of the ty pe 1C. One can easily verify that there exists a mo nom orphism

/ : (£?, .S')- » ( £ ? , .S') such that the equality

c(inl({.r G E : J ( x ) ф .с}) = c n r d ( E )

is fulfilled. Similarly, for any infinite subset A' of E. there exists a monom orphism

!l

(V..s'v ) —

( X , S \ ) such that

c a r d ( { x G A : </(x) ф ./•}) = m r d ( X ) .

Consequently, the structure .s'у induced on the set, A' is not almost rigid in the strong sense.

(11)

Л . К 11A RA ZIS 11V ILI

However, we shall see below that som e additional assum ptions about the ty pe £ of a. structure of an infinite, Dedekind com plete, linearly ordered set, im ply tlx-’ ex istence of an infinite substructure almost rigid in the strong sense.

Our further consideration needs two sim ple auxiliary assertions con-cerning linearly ordered sets.

L e m m a 1. Let ( E , < ) b e a D ed e k in d c o m p le t e d en se linearly

or-der ed set a n d let X be a subset o f E dense in E (i.e. ev e ry n o n e m p t y op en s u b i n te r va l o f E i ntersect s X ). T h e n for each increasing m a p p i n g q : .V —> E the re exis ts an increasing m a p p i n g <Г '■ E —* E e x t e n d i n g y. Moreover, i f t h e original m a p p i n g </ is strict ly increasing, t h e n t he m a p p i n g (j* is st ri c t ly increasing, too.

This lem m a is well known and its proof is not difficult. Actually, the required extension </* can be directly defined by the formula

</*(< ) — s u p {y ( .r) : x £ A' a n d x < e },

where с is an arbitrary element of the basic set E. ta king into account the fact that ( E , < ) is a. dense linearly ordered set, we see that if </ is a. strictly increasing m apping , then //* is a strictly increasing mapping, too. We also want to remark that, in general, //* is not the unique extension ol //.

L e m m a 2. Let ( E , < ) be a De d e k in d c o mp l e t e den se linearly

or-d ereor-d set. II' t h e basic set E conta ins at least t wo or-d ist i nc t ele men t s, t h en c n r d ( E ) > c. where с d en ot es t h e card ina lit y o f t h e co n t i n u u m .

This lemma is well known and can easily be proved by the standard m etho d using a dyadic system of closed bounded subintervals of h .

Let ( E . <) be an ordered set. We say that this set is isodyne if the cardinality of each nonem pty open subinterval of E is equal to the cardinality ol the basic set E. In other words, ( E , < ) is isodyne il and only if the space E is isodyne with respect to the order topology. For ex am ple, the real line R is an isodyne linearly ordered set.

Let us denote by the symbol M o n ( E , E ) the set of all strictly in-creasing mappings from the ordered set E into itself.

(12)

L e m m a 3 . Is't. ( E , < ) be au infi nite i so d yn e ordered set, let 7 be

t he least ordinal n u m b e r c orrespo n di ng to t h e ca rdi na li ty o f t h e basic set E a n d let

M o n ( E , E ) = {(j0 : a < 7}.

Th e n t here ex i st s a subset

Л = {.r„ : tv < 7}

o f E sa t i sfy in g t h e following relations:

(1) t h e f a mi ly {./•,, : n < 7) is injective; in particular, c u r d ( X ) =

c a r d ( E) ;

(2) A is d ense e ve r yw h er e in E;

(.'{) loi■ each ordinal n < -, a n d for a n y t wo ordinals /i < rv, 0 < o , we h av e ,r0 ф ;Ц)(х0 ) a n d ,rn ф //J1 ( ).

I'roof. T h e argument is very similar to the proof of Proposition 1.

Namely, we shall construct, by the m ethod of transfimte recursion, an injective 7 sequence of points

{.r„ : (У < 7} (.r0 6 E).

For this purpose denote by { I ], : c\ < 7 } the family of all nonem pty open subintervals of E and let {</„ : о < 7} be the family of all m onomorphism s from E into E. Of course, without loss of generality, we can assum e that /д, is the identity transformation of the set E. Suppose now that, for an ordinal rv < 7. the partial o -sequence { xp :

ß < 0} has already been constructed. Let us deline two sets:

/I = {<l.i(x(i) : ji '< о . 0 < n }.

H = {.'/,7 ' (•'•(?) : ß < 0. 0 < n }.

Obviously, the cardinality of the set /I U H is strictly less than the cardinality ol the set E. Since E is isodyne, there exists an element x belonging to the set

(13)

Let us put x n — x . Therefore, using the mot hod of transfm ite réclusion, we are able to construct a certain 7-sequen ce of elem ents ol E. It is clear tha t this sequence is injective, and if we put

X = { x a : a < 7},

then it is not difficult to check th at the set Л' is a required one. Slightly changing the a bove argum ent we can prove that the required set A satisfies also the follow ing relation:

(4) c a r d ( X П V ) = c u r d ( E ) , for each nonem pty open subinterval V

o f E.

Of course, relation (4) is m uch stronger than relation (2). T his ends the proot.

Now, we can form ulate one ol m any results dealing w ith the ex is-tence of alm o st rigid substructures ol t he original m a them atical struc-ture. Here we restrict, our consideration to the theory of Dedekind co m plete dense linearly o lden'd sets. I he classical ex am p le ol such a set is the real line R with its natural ordering. Another standard ex am p le is the so called Suslin line (see E xam ple 4 below ).

P r o p o s i t i o n 3 . Let ( E . <) be an infinite' d en se is o d yn e D e d e k in d

c o m p le te lin early ordered set a n d let

c n r d ( M o n ( E , E )) < c u r d ( E ) . In ot her words, w e can w rite

M o n ( E , E ) = {и« : о < 7},

wh ere 7 is th e least ordinal n u m b e r co rrespo nd ing to th e ca rd in ality

o f th e basic set E . Let X he a subset, o f E sa tisfy in g relatio ns (J), (2) a n d (:i) o f L e m m a 3. T h e n th e s tr u c tu re ( X , < ) is almost, rigid in th e s tro n g sense.

Proof. Let <1 he any m onom orphism from X into A . B y L em m a 1, there ex ists a m onom orphism //* which acts from E in to E and exten ds

4. Taking into account th e definition of the set A . we have

(14)

C onsequently, we ;ilso have

<•<//■</( {.r G .V : </(.r) ф .;■}) < a i r d ( X ) , and tin* structure (Л , < ) is alm o st rigid in th e strong sense.

E x a m p le 3 . Let ns pul /? = R and let us take as < the usual ordering o f R . T hen it is easy to see that Proposition 3 can directly be applied in this case. Hence, there ex ists an everyw here dense subset X of R such tha t c a r d ( X ) is equal to the cardinality of the continuum and every strictly increasing m apping, acting from X into A , is al-m ost id entity transforal-m ation of Л . We can also assual-m e th at, for each nonem pty open subinterval V of R , the intersection X П V has the cardinality of the continuum . Moreover, we can even assum e that A is a B ernstein subset of R (for the definition o f a Bernstein subset of the real line and for the properties of such subsets, see [2], [3], [4] or [5]).

W e also can consider a m ore general situa tio n. Nam ely, let к be an infinite cardinal num ber such th at, for every cardinal A < к, we have the inequality

2a <

Then there are dense isodyne Dedekind com plete linearly ordered sets

( E , <) sa tisfying the following conditions:

1 ) ra rd( E ) = 2":

2) E contains a dense subset I) with c a r d ( D ) = к.

For various exam ples of ( E . < ) with the above-m entioned proper-ties, see e.g. the m onograph of Sierpiński [7].

(Consequently, for such ( E, < ) we have the inequality

c a r d { M o n ( E , E ) ) < r a r d ( E ) .

Thus, we m ay apply directly Proposition 3 to { E . < ) . A pply ing this proposition we obtain that there exists a subset A’ of E such that

a) c a r d ( X ) = c a rd ( E ) \

b) A is dense everyw here in E\

c) X is iso dv ne w ith respect to the induced order;

d) A is alm ost rigid in the strong sense with respect to the induced order.

(15)

E x a m p le 4 . Let us recall that a Siislin line is a nonem pty Dedekind co m p lete dense linearly ordered set (/'J, < ) , w ithout the first and the last elem ents, sa tisfy ing the Suslin condition (i.e. the co untable chain condition which says th at every disjoint fam ily of nonem pty open subin-tervals of E is at m ost countable) and nonseparable in its order topol-ogy. It is well known th at the ex isten ce o f a Suslin line is co nsistent with the usual a xio m a tic set theory Z F C and is not provable from this theory (see, for instance, [6]). Let us consider briefly the question about the ca rdinality o f a Suslin line E. On one hand, by L em m a 2, we have the inequality a i r d ( E ) > c. On the other hand, we have the inequality c it rd (E ) < c. T he latter fact can directly be deduced from each o f the following tw o well known results:

1) the Erdńs-Rado theorem of the com binatorial set theory;

2) the Arhangelskii theorem about, the cardinality of a com pact topological space sa tisfy in g the first countability axiom .

N otice also th a t, by a classical result of D.K urepa, any Suslin line E contains an everyw here dense subset whose cardinality is equal to the first, unco untable cardinal number ш\ (the above-m entioned inequality

card( E ) < с follows im m ediately from this result). T hus, we conclude

that the equality

c a r d ( E ) = с

holds, and we can deduce that any Suslin line E is an isodyne linearly ordered set.

Let us remark that R.Jensen showed, assum ing the Axiom of Con-struct ibility. the ex istence of a rigid Suslin line E (th e m entioned axiom with its various consequences and applications is discussed in detail, e.g., in [(>]). Furtherm ore, V.I.Fukson proved in [8] that if the Axiom of ( Construct ibility holds, then there ex ists a Suslin line E such tha t, for any continuous m apping

/ : E -> E .

at least one of th e following tw o assertions is true: a) J is a constant m apping;

(16)

A nother interesting exa m p le (in Z F C ) ol‘ a Dedekind com plete dense iso dyne linearly ordered set is the so called long line of A lexa n-drov. T his line is a nonseparable one-dim ensional connected m anifold containing an everywhere dense subset of cardinality ш\.

E x a m p le 5 . Let u> denote the first infinite cardinal num ber. It is obvious tha t if the Continuum H ypothesis holds, then we have

c _ -)ы < 2Ш[.

T he Second C ontinuum H ypothesis is the following set-theo retica l as-sertion:

2W = 2U/| ( S C I f ) .

T his assertion was considered, m any years ago, by N .Luzin who also exp ected that it is consistent with the usual axiom s o f Set Theory, likely as th e classical ( Continuum I lyp oth esis. Indeed, much later a num ber of m odels o f Set T heory were constructed in which the Second Continuum H ypothesis holds (see. lor instance, [()]). In particular, there are m odels o f Set T heory in which we have the following equalities:

A ctually, il we start with an arbitrary countable tra nsitive m odel of Z F C , satisfying th e G eneralized Continuum H ypothesis, and apply the Cohen lorcing to it, then we obtain a m odel of Z F C in which the abo ve-m entio ned equalities are fulfilled (for details, see [(>]).

A ssum e now that, the Second Continuum H ypothesis holds.

Let ( E , < ) be an arbitrary Dedekind com plete dense isodyne lin-early ordered set containing an everyw here dense subset o f cardinality

uJ\. Then we have

c a v d (E ) — 2Ш| = 2Ш = с. Also, it, is not difficult, to verify that

c u r , l ( M , m ( E , E ) ) < 2m = 2" = c.

1 herefore, in this situation we can apply Proposition 3 again and we conclude th at, in theory ( Z F C ) & ( $ C H ) , each linearly ordered set.

(17)

( E , < ) with the properties form ulated above contains an everyw here

dense subset Л' sa tisfy in g the following relations: a) c a r d ( X ) = c a r d ( E ) \

b) A’ is alm ost rigid in th e strong sense (w ith respect to th e induced order).

In additio n, we see that the required subset X of E can be con-structed so tha t, for an arbitrary nonem pty open subinterval V o f E , we have the equality

c n r d ( X П V ) = r a r d ( E) .

M oreover, we can even assum e that X is a Bernstein ty p e subset of E , i.e.

c n r d ( X П P ) = c a r d { ( E \ X ) f ) P ) = c a r d ( E ) ,

for every no nem pty perfect subset P of E .

E x a m p l e 6. T he preceding exa m p le ran be generalized to som e situa tio ns where we have a D edekind com plete dense isodyne linearly ordered set [ E, <) with

c a r d ( E ) > c.

More precisely, let к and A be any two infinite cardinal num bers sa tis-fying the equality

2Л = к.

Further, let ( E , < ) lie a Dedekind com plete dense iso dy ne linearly or-dered set sa tisfy in g the next two conditions:

1) i'u rd (E ) = Л"

2) E contains a dense subset Г) with n i r d ( D ) = A. Then there ex ists a dense subset .V o f E such that a) r a r d ( X ) = c a rd ( E ) ;

b) A' is alm ost rigid in the strong sense (w ith respect to the induced order).

M oreover, we m ay a ssum e tha t, for any nonem pty open subinterval

V o f th e set /v, th e equality

c a r d ( V П A') = c a r d ( E )

(18)

Re f e r e n c e s

[1]. N . B o u r b a k i , S e t T h e o r y , M o s c o w , 19(55, (in R us s ia n , t r a n s la t io n fr om Fre nch ).

[2]. K .K u r a t o w s k i, Topol ogy, vo l. 1, M o s c o w , 196 6, (in R u s s ia n) .

[3]. J . O x t o b y , M e a s u r e a n d C a t e g o r y , S p r in g e r - V er la g, N e w Y or k, 19 80, ( 2 - n d e d . ) .

[4]. J .M o r g a n II, F'niiil S e t Th e or y , Marc el D ek ker, Inc.. N e w York an d B a sel, 1990.

[5]. .!.( ichdii. A .K h a r a z is h v il i. li.W o g lor z , S u b s e t s o f tin li r a i Line, Part, 1, Łod ź U n iv e r s it y Press. Łó dź. 1995. [6]. Ha n d bo o k o f M a t h e m a t i c a l Logie, N o r t h - H o lla n d , A m s t e r d a m , 1977. [7]. W . S ie r p iń s k i, C a r d i n a l a m i O r d i n a l N u m b e r s , PYVN, W a r s z aw a , 1958. [8]. V . I .F u k s o n , A s t r o n g l y r i gi d c o n t i nu u m , in: S t u d i e s iu Set. T h e o r y a n d N on - c las s ic al L og ic s, M o s c o w , 197 6, 1 2 3 - 1 2 6 , (in R u ss ia n ) . [9]. R.M.SImrt .t, ( i r o up s o f m e a s u r a b l e a u t o m o r p h i s m s f o r s p a c e s o f f i ni t e type, C o n t e m p o r a r y Mat h e m a t i c s 9 4 ( 1 9 8 9 ) , 2 9 1 - 3 0 7 .

A I < kxa ii(1er K h a razish vili

O P R A W I E S Z T Y W N Y C H S T R U K T U R A C H M A T E M A T Y C Z N Y C H

YV pracy rozważa sir prawic szty w ne struktury m atem atyczne. Zostały zbadane pewne własności takich struktur.

I n s t it u t e o f A pp lied M a t h e m a t ic s U n iv e r s it y o f T b il is i U n ive r s it y Str . 2 , 3 8 0 0 4 3 T b ilis i 4 3 , G e o r g ia

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

In the section 2 we define the idea of the weak-normality of jn almost paracontact structure 2 on M requiring some almost product structures Fi (2), F2(2) onAf to be integrable,

We will get infor- mation from all the ideals, by means of Theorem 1.1 and noting that in fact an ideal is, in some sense, a divisor of its elements.. In this way, we give a new

Montgomery and Vaughan [27] have observed that results like Theorem 1 can help to show that a short interval contains lots of Goldbach numbers... (even numbers representable as a sum

In other words, a change of sings of coefficients in Fourier series of continuous even functions with the period 2n and the replacement of cosinus by sinus is

For the first type, we study the existence of geodesics in the space of volume forms associated with a real closed Riemannian manifold, which is a counterpart of the geodesic problem

In order to distinguish between a case when the environment is simply a source of effective noise that is independent of the dynamics or even presence of the qubits

“almost all” permutations have infinitely many infinite cycles and only finitely many finite cycles; this set of permutations comprises countably many conjugacy classes, each of

Fundamental rights, as guaranteed by the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and as they result from the constitutional traditions