• Nie Znaleziono Wyników

C O L L O Q U I U M M A T H E M A T I C U M VOL. LXII 1991 FASC. 2

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "C O L L O Q U I U M M A T H E M A T I C U M VOL. LXII 1991 FASC. 2"

Copied!
6
0
0

Pełen tekst

(1)

VOL. LXII 1991 FASC. 2

SOME ADDITIVE PROPERTIES OF SPECIAL SETS OF REALS

BY

IRENEUSZ R E C L A W (GDA ´ NSK)

D. H. Fremlin and J. Jasi´ nski [4] have proved a relative consistency of the existence of a very thin set of reals. In this context they have asked (private communication) the following question: Given a universally null set X ⊆ R and a Borel measure µ on R, does it follow that there exists a Borel set B ⊆ R covering X such that for every t ∈ R, µ(B + t) = 0?

Note that the answer is in the affirmative if X has strong measure zero (due to the uniform continuity of Borel measures). In Theorem 1 we provide a negative answer to this question.

The thin set of Fremlin and Jasi´ nski mentioned above preserves many properties of thinness under linear sums. Fremlin and Jasi´ nski asked whether its linear sums with any universally null set are universally null.

In Theorem 2 we show that the answer is in the negative.

For the definition of strong measure zero sets and basic properties of other special sets considered in this paper see A. W. Miller [9] or J. B.

Brown and G. V. Cox [1]. Recall only that a set X ⊆ R k is universally null (X ∈ β) if for every Borel measure µ (continuous probability measure on the family of all Borel subsets of R k ), µ (X) = 0. For X, Y ⊆ R we set X + Y = {x + y : x ∈ X ∧ y ∈ Y } and X − Y = {x − y : x ∈ X ∧ y ∈ Y }.

Most of the results of this note are based on von Neumann’s theorem that there exists a perfect set of reals which is linearly independent over the rationals [11]. The basic technical lemma is the following:

Lemma 1. Let C and D be F σ (resp. compact ) subsets of R. Suppose that X ⊆ C and (C − X) ∩ (D − D) = {0}. Then

(a) + : X ×D → X +D is a Borel isomorphism (resp. homeomorphism), (b) if y x = d x + x, d x ∈ D, x ∈ X, then Y = {y x : x ∈ X}

is the preimage of X by a one-to-one Borel (resp. continuous) function and {d x : x ∈ X} ⊆ Y − X; in particular , if X is universally null , so is Y .

P r o o f. (a) Clearly + is continuous on C ×D. Since (C −X)∩(D−D) =

(2)

{0} we have

X × D ⊆{(c, d) ∈ C × D :

(∀(c 0 , d 0 ) ∈ C × D)((c 0 , d 0 ) 6= (c, d) ⇒ +(c 0 , d 0 ) 6= +(c, d))}.

So, + is one-to-one on X × D. Moreover, for any F ⊆ C × D, +[F ∩ (X × D)] = +[F ] ∩ +[X × D] = +[F ] ∩ (X + D).

If F is F σ (resp. closed) then so is +[F ]. It follows that + sends relative F σ (resp. closed) subsets of X × D to relative F σ (resp. closed) subsets of X + D.

(b) Note that by (a), y x 7→ (x, d x ) is a Borel (resp. continuous) function.

Also (x, d x ) 7→ x, being a projection, is continuous.

Theorem 1. Assume that there exists a universally null set X with |X| = c . Then there exists a Borel measure µ on R and a universally null set Y ⊆ R such that whenever B is a Borel set covering Y , then µ(B + t) = 1 for some t ∈ R.

P r o o f. Let C and D be disjoint, perfect subsets of R such that C ∪ D is linearly independent over the rationals (von Neumann [11]). We can assume that X ⊆ C. Let B x , x ∈ X, be all Borel sets. For every x ∈ X, choose y x ∈ C + x so that y x 6∈ B x whenever (C + x) \ B x 6= ∅. By Lemma 1, Y = {y x : x ∈ X} is universally null. Also, y x ∈ B x for any Borel set B x ⊇ Y , so (C + x) \ B x = ∅ by our choice of y x , and hence C ⊆ B x − x. It follows that if for a Borel measure µ we have µ(C) = 1 then µ satisfies the conclusion of the theorem.

Theorem 2. Let X ⊆ R, |X| = c, be a universally null set for which there exists a meagre F σ set C ⊇ X such that C − X is meagre. Then there exists a universally null set Y ⊂ R such that X + Y is not universally null.

P r o o f. By a theorem of Mycielski [10], if G ⊆ R is a dense G δ with 0 ∈ G then there exists a perfect set D ⊆ R such that D − D ⊆ G. So, in our case, we can find a perfect set D such that (C − X) ∩ (D − D) = {0}.

Let {d x : x ∈ X} = D. By Lemma 1, Y = {x + d x : x ∈ X} is universally null and D ⊆ Y − X. So Y − X is not universally null.

Theorem 3. Assume Martin’s Axiom. For every X ⊆ R with |X| = c there exists a universally null set Y ⊆ R such that X + Y is not universally null.

P r o o f. Suppose that X ⊆ R with |X| = c is such that X + Y is universally null for every universally null set Y ⊆ R. Let µ α , α < c, be all Borel measures on R. For each α, let P α ξ , ξ < c, be all dense G δ sets of µ α

measure zero, and let Q ξ α = T

η≤ξ P α η .

(3)

Claim 1. For each α there is ξ(α) such that X + Q ξ(α) α ⊆ P α ξ(α) . P r o o f. Fix α. If X + Q ξ α 6⊆ P α ξ , then choose y ξ ∈ Q ξ α such that X + y ξ 6⊆ P α ξ . If this can be done for all ξ < c, then Y = {y ξ : ξ < c} is a generalized Lusin set, hence a universally null set. Also no P α ξ covers X + Y , so µ α (X + Y ) > 0 and X + Y is not universally null, a contradiction.

Claim 2. There are α and t ∈ R such that |X \ (P α ξ(α) + t)| = c.

P r o o f. Suppose not, and let R = {t α : α < c}. Let x α ∈ X ∩ (t α + T

β≤α P β ξ(β) ) and y α = t α − x α . Then −y α ∈ T

β≤α P β ξ(β) , so Y = {y α : α < c} is universally null. Also X + Y = R, so X + Y is not universally null, contrary to our assumption.

Now, fix α and t as in Claim 2. Let X 0 = X \ (P α ξ(α) + t) and C = R \ (P α ξ(α) + t). Then |X 0 | = c, X 0 ⊆ C, C is a meagre F σ set and C − X 0 ⊆ R \ (Q ξ(α) α + t) is also meagre. So, by Theorem 2, there is a universally null set Y such that X 0 + Y , and hence X + Y , is not universally null, a contradiction.

Our next aim is to prove the existence of some special subspaces of R.

Similar problems where investigated independently by W. F. Pfeffer and K. Prikry [12]. Let us recall some definitions.

Let X ⊆ R k . X is called a λ-set (X ∈ λ) if every countable subset of X is a relative G δ . X is called always of the first category (X ∈ K ) if for any perfect set P the set X ∩ P is meagre in P . X ∈ e K if for every Y ⊆ R n such that there exists a one-to-one Borel function f : Y → X, we have Y ∈ K .

For W ⊆ R let W (n) = {(w 1 , . . . , w n ) ∈ W n : w i < w j for i < j ≤ n}.

Lemma 2. Let Z ⊆ R be a perfect set linearly independent over Q and let τ = (q 1 , . . . , q n ) be a finite sequence of non-zero rational numbers. Then the function f τ : Z (n) → R, f τ (z 1 , . . . , z n ) = P n

i=1 q i z i , is continuous, one- to-one, and for every F σ set F ⊆ Z (n) the set f τ (F ) is an F σ in R.

P r o o f. The continuity of f τ is obvious. The linear independence of Z implies that f τ is one-to-one. The last assertion follows from the continuity of f τ and σ-compactness of Z (n) .

For X ⊆ R let ((X)) be the linear space over Q generated by X.

Theorem 4. If Z ⊆ R is a perfect set linearly independent over Q then for every X ⊆ Z the following hold :

1) If X ∈ β then ((X)) ∈ β.

2) If X ∈ λ then ((X)) ∈ λ.

3) If X ∈ e K and |X| ≤ ω 1 then ((X)) ∈ e K .

(4)

P r o o f. Observe that if X ⊆ Z then ((X)) = [

n∈ω\{0}

[

τ ∈(Q\{0})

n

f τ (X (n) ) ∪ {0}.

If X ∈ β then X (n) ∈ β, and since f τ is a Borel isomorphism, f τ (X (n) ) ∈ β. Thus also ((X)) ∈ β.

If X ∈ λ then X (n) ∈ λ, and, by Lemma 2, f τ (X (n) ) ∈ λ. Notice that f τ (X (n) ) ⊆ f τ (Z (n) ) and whenever σ ∈ (Q \ {0}) k and τ ∈ (Q \ {0}) n , σ 6= τ implies f τ (Z (n) ) ∩ f σ (Z (k) ) = ∅. In this case a countable union of λ-sets is a λ-set. Thus ((X)) ∈ λ.

If X ∈ e K then X (n) ∈ e K (see E. Grzegorek [7]). By Lemma 2, f τ (X (n) ) ∈ e K , and as e K is a σ-ideal we have ((X)) ∈ e K .

The following theorem is a version of a theorem of Erd˝ os, Kunen and Mauldin [2]. Our theorem is weaker but no hypothesis besides ZFC is re- quired.

Theorem 5. There exist universally null , linear spaces X, Y ⊆ R over Q such that X ∩ Y = {0} and X + Y is not universally null.

P r o o f. Let C 1 and D 1 be disjoint, perfect subsets of R such that C 1 ∪D 1

is linearly independent over the rationals (von Neumann [11]). By a result of Grzegorek [6], there are sets X 1 ⊆ C 1 and Z 1 ⊆ D 1 such that |X 1 | = |Z 1 |, X 1 is universally null and Z 1 is not universally null. Let g : X 1 → Z 1 be a bijection. Let C = ((C 1 )), D = ((D 1 )), X = ((X 1 )), Z = ((Z 1 )). Then C and D are F σ sets, (C − C) ∩ (D − D) = {0} and X ⊆ C, Z ⊆ D. Moreover, g can be extended to a linear isomorphism between X and Z. By Lemma 2, X is universally null. Let Y = {x + g(x) : x ∈ X}. Then Y is a linear space over the rationals, X ∩ Y = {0}, and, by Lemma 1, Y is universally null.

Also Y − X ⊇ Z, so Y − X is not universally null.

We conclude with a number of results saying that R may be expressed as a linear sum of some special sets and Lebesgue null sets.

Let S ⊆ S

n∈ω\{0} P (R n ). We say that S has property (∗) if whenever Y ∈ S and f : X → Y is a one-to-one continuous function, then X ∈ S.

Observe that β, λ, e K , β ∩ λ, and e K ∩ β have property (∗).

Let m be the Lebesgue measure on R.

Theorem 6. Let Z ⊆ R be a perfect set linearly independent over Q, let C and D be perfect disjoint compact subsets of Z and let S be a family with property (∗). Suppose there exist T ⊆ D, G ⊆ R with m(G) = 0, T + G = R, and a set of reals X ∈ S with |X| = |T |. Then there exists a set of reals Y ∈ S and a set V ⊆ R with m(V ) = 0 such that Y + V = R.

Recall that a set Y ⊆ R does not have strong measure zero iff there

exists a meagre set V ⊆ R such that Y + V = R (see F. Galvin, J. Mycielski

(5)

and R. Solovay [5]). The corollaries below show that certain special sets are not necessarily of strong first category (see [9], p. 210).

The proof of the following lemma is similar to the proof of Lemma 9 of P. Erd˝ os, K. Kunen and R. Mauldin [2].

Lemma 3. For every H ⊆ R with m(H) = 0 and for every perfect set E there exists a perfect set E 1 ⊆ E such that m(H − E 1 ) = 0.

P r o o f o f T h e o r e m 6 . Let E 1 ⊆ C be such that m(G − E 1 ) = 0.

We may assume that X ⊆ E 1 . Let g : X onto → T . As S has property (∗), graph(g) ∈ S. The function h : E 1 × D → E 1 + D, h(e, d) = e + d, is a homeomorphism (Lemma 1). Let Y = h(graph(g)) and V = G−E 1 . Clearly Y ∈ S and m(V ) = 0. We will show that V +Y = R. If z ∈ R then there are t ∈ T and a ∈ G such that z = t + a. There is x ∈ X such that g(x) = t, so x + t ∈ Y . Obviously a − x ∈ G − E 1 = V , thus (a − x) + (x + t) = z ∈ V + Y . Lemma 4 (P. Erd˝ os, K. Kunen and R. Mauldin). If T ⊆ R is not always of first category, then there is a set G with m(G) = 0 such that T + G = R.

P r o o f. See the proof of Theorem 3 of [2].

Corollary 1. There are Y ∈ e K and G ⊆ R with m(G) = 0 such that Y + G = R.

P r o o f. By a theorem of E. Grzegorek [7] there are sets T 6∈ K and X ∈ e K such that |T | = |X|. We can assume that T ⊆ D. The statement now follows from Lemma 4 and Theorem 6.

Recall that X ⊆ R k is called a Q-set if every subset of X is a relative F σ .

Corollary 2. It is consistent that there exist a Q-set Y ⊆ R and G ⊆ R with m(G) = 0 such that Y + G = R.

P r o o f. Notice that the family of Q-sets has property (∗). W. G. Fleiss- ner and A. W. Miller [3] proved that it is consistent that there exist a Q-set X and a Lusin set T 0 with |T 0 | < |X|. It follows that there are a set T ⊆ D of second category in D and a Q-set X such that |T | < |X|.

R e m a r k. Similar results for the families λ, K ∩ β, λ ∩ β, etc. may be obtained under the assumption of CH or MA.

The author wishes to express his thanks to Edward Grzegorek and Jakub Jasi´ nski for fruitful discussions.

Especially, the author would like to express his gratitude to the referee

for simplifying some proofs, in particular for a very elegant and nice version

of Lemma 1.

(6)

REFERENCES

[1] J. B. B r o w n and G. V. C o x, Classical theory of totally imperfect spaces, Real Anal.

Exchange 7 (1981/82), 185–232.

[2] P. E r d ˝ o s, K. K u n e n and R. M a u l d i n, Some additive properties of sets of real numbers, Fund. Math. 113 (1981), 187–199.

[3] W. G. F l e i s s n e r and A. W. M i l l e r, On Q-sets, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 78 (1980), 280–284.

[4] D. H. F r e m l i n and J. J a s i ´ n s k i, G δ -covers and large thin sets of reals, Proc.

London Math. Soc. (3) 53 (1986), 518–538.

[5] F. G a l v i n, J. M y c i e l s k i and R. S o l o v a y, Strong measure zero sets, Notices Amer. Math. Soc. 26 (1979), A-280.

[6] E. G r z e g o r e k, Solution of a problem of Banach on σ-fields without continuous measures, Bull. Acad. Polon. Sci. S´ er. Sci. Math. 28 (1980), 7–10.

[7] —, Always of the first category sets, in: Proc. 12th Winter School on Abstract Analysis, Srn´ı 15–29 January, 1984, Section Topology, Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo (2) Suppl. 6 (1984), 139–147.

[8] K. K u r a t o w s k i, Topology I , Academic Press, New York, and PWN, Warszawa 1966.

[9] A. W. M i l l e r, Special subsets of the real line, in: Handbook of Set -Theoretic Topol- ogy, K. Kunen and J. E. Vaughan (eds.), North-Holland, Amsterdam 1984, 201–233.

[10] J. M y c i e l s k i, Independent sets in topological algebras, Fund. Math. 55 (1964), 139–147.

[11] J. v o n N e u m a n n, Ein System algebraisch unabh¨ angiger Zahlen, Math. Ann. 99 (1928), 134–141.

[12] W. F. P f e f f e r and K. P r i k r y, Small spaces, Proc. London Math. Soc. (3) 58 (1989), 417–438.

INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF GDA ´ NSK WITA STWOSZA 57 80-952 GDA ´ NSK, POLAND

Re¸ cu par la R´ edaction le 19.12.1988

en version d´ efinitive le 30.8.1990

Cytaty

Powiązane dokumenty

The author would like to thank the referee for his valuable

In this paper we are concerned with the compact- ification G P of the homeomorphism group of the pseudo-arc P , which is obtained by the method of Kennedy.. We prove that G P

In particular, it turns out that the mixed measure-category product of ideals (i.e. the product of the ideal of all meager sets and the ideal of all sets having measure zero)

For a special formally real Jordan algebra U there exists a Euclidean space E and a Jordan algebra injective homomorphism φ : U → Sym + (E) of U into the formally real Jordan algebra

Si on note H 1 le sous-groupe de R form´e par tous les nombres r´eels x tels que la s´ erie de terme g´ en´ eral kxn!k 2 converge, cela se traduit donc par le r´ esultat suivant,

If R is continuous, we can extend it by continuity onto the whole of X, and since relations (2) will be satisfied for all x in X, by continuity of the involved operators, we can

We shall prove (Section 5) that (∗) and (∗∗∗) are equivalent at every point of a 4-dimensional warped product manifold at which the tensor S − (K/n)g does not vanish, where K is

We denote by ∇, e R, R, S and κ the Levi-Civit` a connection, the curvature tensor, the Riemann–Christoffel cur- vature tensor, the Ricci tensor and the scalar curvature of (M,